forking and dimensions in pseudofinite structures
play

Forking and dimensions in pseudofinite structures Daro Garca - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Forking and dimensions in pseudofinite structures Daro Garca University of Leeds. Logic Seminar - School of Mathematics. Leeds, UK. February 22, 2017 Model theory, forking and dimension Model Theory: tame vs. wild structures Example (The


  1. Forking and dimensions in pseudofinite structures Darío García University of Leeds. Logic Seminar - School of Mathematics. Leeds, UK. February 22, 2017

  2. Model theory, forking and dimension

  3. Model Theory: tame vs. wild structures Example (The quintessential example of a tame structure) Consider the theory of the complex field which can be effectively axiomatized by a finite number of axiom schemes: 1. Field axioms (finite in number). 2. ∀ x 1 , . . . , x n ∃ y ( y n + x 1 y n − 1 + · · · + x n = 0 ) , for n = 1 , 2 , 3 , . . . 3. 1 + · · · + 1 � = 0 , for n = 1 , 2 , 3 , . . . . � �� � n -times Example (The quintessential example of a wild structure) Gödel proved that Th ( Z , + , · ) cannot be effectively described in any reasonable way, so in contrast to the field of complex numbers, the ring of integers is wild. (But Z as ordered additive group is tame again!)

  4. ◮ We use here “tame” and “wild” very informally , to suggest the distinction between good and bad model-theoretic behavior. ◮ Shelah defined several dividing lines (stability, simplicity, NIP, NTP 2 , etc.) to distinguish “tame” from “wild” structures in terms of the (non-)existence of combinatorial configurations of their definable sets. ◮ Gödel’s work is often characterized as saying that those structures M for which Th ( M ) can be effectively axiomatizable are uninteresting. ◮ However, even in extremely “wild” subjects (such as number theory), the solution to difficult problems often uses illuminating explorations into tame territory!

  5. ◮ We use here “tame” and “wild” very informally , to suggest the distinction between good and bad model-theoretic behavior. ◮ Shelah defined several dividing lines (stability, simplicity, NIP, NTP 2 , etc.) to distinguish “tame” from “wild” structures in terms of the (non-)existence of combinatorial configurations of their definable sets. ◮ Gödel’s work is often characterized as saying that those structures M for which Th ( M ) can be effectively axiomatizable are uninteresting. ◮ However, even in extremely “wild” subjects (such as number theory), the solution to difficult problems often uses illuminating explorations into tame territory! model theory = geography of tame mathematics . E. Hrushovski c �

  6. Model theory=geography of tame mathematics

  7. Model theory=geography of tame mathematics Simple Rosy ( Z , + , · , < ) ZFC NTP 2 Pseudofinite fields Pseudoreal closed fields Random Graph Stable O-minimal ( Q , < ) ( Z , + , < ) ( Q p , + , · ) ( Z , +) NIP ( R , + , · , < ) Strongly minimal ( C , + , · , 0 , 1 ) A more detailed map at www. forkinganddividing. com (due to Gabriel Conant)

  8. Dividing and forking. Definition Let φ ( x , b ) be a formula and A ⊆ M be a set of parameters. 1. We say that φ ( x , b ) divides over A if there is an infinite sequence � b i : i < ω � of elements such that: ◮ tp ( b i / A ) = tp ( b / A ) . ◮ The set of formulas { φ ( x , b i ) : i < ω } is k -inconsistent for some k < ω . 2. We say that a formula θ ( x ) (possibly with parameters) forks over A if θ ( x ) implies a finite disjunction of formulas that divide over A .

  9. Example 1. In any theory T with infinite models, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ x = b divides over A whenever b �∈ acl ( A ) .

  10. Example 1. In any theory T with infinite models, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ x = b divides over A whenever b �∈ acl ( A ) . It is enough to take a sequence � b i : i < ω � of different conjugates of b over A . The set of formulas { x = b i : i < ω } will be 2-inconsistent.

  11. Example 1. In any theory T with infinite models, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ x = b divides over A = ∅ . 2. For the theory ACF of algebraically closed fields, the formula φ ( x , π ) ≡ x 2 = π divides over A = Q .

  12. Example 1. In any theory T with infinite models, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ x = b divides over A = ∅ . 2. For the theory ACF of algebraically closed fields, the formula φ ( x , π ) ≡ x 2 = π divides over A = Q . If � π 1 , π 2 , . . . , � is a sequence of infinitely many distinct transcendental numbers, then we have: ◮ tp ( π i / Q ) = tp ( π/ Q ) . ◮ The set of formulas { x 2 = π i : i < ω } is 3-inconsistent. In fact, one can show that in ACF forking can be characterized by the algebraic formulas.

  13. Example 1. In any theory T with infinite models, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ x = b divides over A = ∅ . 2. For the theory ACF of algebraically closed fields, the formula φ ( x , π ) ≡ x 2 = π divides over A = Q . In fact, one can show that in ACF forking can be characterized by the algebraic formulas. 3. In the theory DLO of dense linear orders, the formula φ ( x ; ab ) ≡ a < x < b divides over A = ∅ .

  14. b b b Example 1. In any theory T with infinite models, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ x = b divides over A = ∅ . 2. For the theory ACF of algebraically closed fields, the formula φ ( x , π ) ≡ x 2 = π divides over A = Q . In fact, one can show that in ACF forking can be characterized by the algebraic formulas. 3. In the theory DLO of dense linear orders, the formula φ ( x ; ab ) ≡ a < x < b divides over A = ∅ . ( ) ( ) ( ) a 1 b 1 a 2 b 2 a 3 b 3 The set of formulas { a i < x < b i : i < ω } is 2-inconsistent.

  15. Example 1. In any theory T with infinite models, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ x = b divides over A = ∅ . 2. For the theory ACF of algebraically closed fields, the formula φ ( x , π ) ≡ x 2 = π divides over A = Q . In fact, one can show that in ACF forking can be characterized by the algebraic formulas. 3. In the theory DLO of dense linear orders, the formula φ ( x ; ab ) ≡ a < x < b divides over A = ∅ . 4. In the theory T E of an equivalence relation with infinitely many infinite classes, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ xEb divides over A = ∅ .

  16. Example 1. In any theory T with infinite models, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ x = b divides over A = ∅ . 2. For the theory ACF of algebraically closed fields, the formula φ ( x , π ) ≡ x 2 = π divides over A = Q . In fact, one can show that in ACF forking can be characterized by the algebraic formulas. 3. In the theory DLO of dense linear orders, the formula φ ( x ; ab ) ≡ a < x < b divides over A = ∅ . 4. In the theory T E of an equivalence relation with infinitely many infinite classes, the formula φ ( x , b ) ≡ xEb divides over A = ∅ . If � b i : i < ω � is a sequence of element in different equivalence classes, then the set of formulas { xEb i : i < ω } is 2-inconsistent (by the transitivity of E ).

  17. Non-Forking independence Definition Given a tuple a , we say that a is independent from B over A if there is no formula φ ( x , b ) ∈ tp ( a / B ) that forks over A . We denote this by a | B ⌣ A ◮ The concept of forking and forking-independence played a crucial role in the Theory of Classification developed by Shelah, especially for stable theories. ◮ Even today, a recurrent theme in model theory is characterize forking in certain known structures in terms of combinatorial or algebraic invariants. ◮ The notion of non-forking independence generalizes several classic notions of independence (algebraic independence, linear independence, among others).

  18. b b b Forking and dimension. Example Consider the formula φ ( x , y ; b ) ≡ y = x + b defined in C 2 . φ ( x , b 3 ) . . . φ ( x , b 2 ) 2-inconsistent φ ( x , b 1 ) b 3 b 2 b 1

  19. This formula divides over ∅ . Intuitively, the set by φ ( x , y ; b ) is small as it defines a set of dimension 1 inside a space of dimension 2.

  20. This formula divides over ∅ . Intuitively, the set by φ ( x , y ; b ) is small as it defines a set of dimension 1 inside a space of dimension 2. Question In those examples when there is a established notion of dimension, can forking-independence be detected by changes (decreasing) of this dimension? As the examples of the complex numbers suggest, an ideal answer to this question would be the following:

  21. This formula divides over ∅ . Intuitively, the set by φ ( x , y ; b ) is small as it defines a set of dimension 1 inside a space of dimension 2. Question In those examples when there is a established notion of dimension, can forking-independence be detected by changes (decreasing) of this dimension? As the examples of the complex numbers suggest, an ideal answer to this question would be the following: c � | B ⇔ dim ( c / B ) < dim ( c / A ) ⌣ A ⇔ There is a set X = φ ( M ; b ) such that c ∈ X and dim ( X ) < dim ( Y ) for every A -definable set Y containing c .

  22. Example 1. In ACF , the notion of dimension is transcendence degree: dim ( a / A ) := transc . deg ( Q ( A , a ) / Q ( A )) . We have √ π � | ⌣ Q Q ( π ) , but also dim ( √ π/ Q ) = transc . deg Q ( √ π ) / Q � � = 1 < dim ( √ π/ Q ( π )) = 0 .

  23. b b b 2. In the theory T E , there is a combinatorial notion of dimension that can be defined recursively by the following rule: Definition The dimension of a point is equal to zero, and dim ( X ) ≥ n + 1 if and only if there are infinitely many disjoints sets Y i contained in X with dim ( Y i ) ≥ n . dim = 2

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend