definability of maximal discrete sets
play

Definability of maximal discrete sets David Schrittesser University - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Definability of maximal discrete sets David Schrittesser University of Copenhagen (Denmark) Arctic Set Theory 3, Kilpisjrvi January 28, 2017 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 1 / 25


  1. Short excursion: Irregular sets of reals We think of maximal discrete sets as a type of irregular set of reals. Some classical regularity properties: Lebesgue measurability Baire property being completely Ramsey (Baire property with respect to the Ellentuck-topology, in [ ω ] ω ) How complicated must a set of reals be in order to be irregular ? analytic sets can usually be shown to be regular In L , there are ∆ 1 2 irregular sets Under large cardinals, all projective sets are regular between these extremes, one can obtain lots of independence results via forcing (some requiring smaller large cardinals) Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 5 / 25

  2. Short excursion: Irregular sets of reals We think of maximal discrete sets as a type of irregular set of reals. Some classical regularity properties: Lebesgue measurability Baire property being completely Ramsey (Baire property with respect to the Ellentuck-topology, in [ ω ] ω ) How complicated must a set of reals be in order to be irregular ? analytic sets can usually be shown to be regular In L , there are ∆ 1 2 irregular sets Under large cardinals, all projective sets are regular between these extremes, one can obtain lots of independence results via forcing (some requiring smaller large cardinals) Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 5 / 25

  3. Short excursion: Irregular sets of reals We think of maximal discrete sets as a type of irregular set of reals. Some classical regularity properties: Lebesgue measurability Baire property being completely Ramsey (Baire property with respect to the Ellentuck-topology, in [ ω ] ω ) How complicated must a set of reals be in order to be irregular ? analytic sets can usually be shown to be regular In L , there are ∆ 1 2 irregular sets Under large cardinals, all projective sets are regular between these extremes, one can obtain lots of independence results via forcing (some requiring smaller large cardinals) Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 5 / 25

  4. Short excursion: Irregular sets of reals We think of maximal discrete sets as a type of irregular set of reals. Some classical regularity properties: Lebesgue measurability Baire property being completely Ramsey (Baire property with respect to the Ellentuck-topology, in [ ω ] ω ) How complicated must a set of reals be in order to be irregular ? analytic sets can usually be shown to be regular In L , there are ∆ 1 2 irregular sets Under large cardinals, all projective sets are regular between these extremes, one can obtain lots of independence results via forcing (some requiring smaller large cardinals) Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 5 / 25

  5. Instances of maximal discrete sets Binary Transversals for equivalence relations Mad families Maximal eventually different families Maximal independent families of sets (or of functions) Maximal orthogonal families of measures (mofs) Higher arity Hamel basis (basis of R over Q ) Maximal cofinitary groups (mcgs) This talk is about mofs, mcgs and Hamel bases. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 6 / 25

  6. Instances of maximal discrete sets Binary Transversals for equivalence relations Mad families Maximal eventually different families Maximal independent families of sets (or of functions) Maximal orthogonal families of measures (mofs) Higher arity Hamel basis (basis of R over Q ) Maximal cofinitary groups (mcgs) This talk is about mofs, mcgs and Hamel bases. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 6 / 25

  7. Instances of maximal discrete sets Binary Transversals for equivalence relations Mad families Maximal eventually different families Maximal independent families of sets (or of functions) Maximal orthogonal families of measures (mofs) Higher arity Hamel basis (basis of R over Q ) Maximal cofinitary groups (mcgs) This talk is about mofs, mcgs and Hamel bases. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 6 / 25

  8. Instances of maximal discrete sets Binary Transversals for equivalence relations Mad families Maximal eventually different families Maximal independent families of sets (or of functions) Maximal orthogonal families of measures (mofs) Higher arity Hamel basis (basis of R over Q ) Maximal cofinitary groups (mcgs) This talk is about mofs, mcgs and Hamel bases. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 6 / 25

  9. Instances of maximal discrete sets Binary Transversals for equivalence relations Mad families Maximal eventually different families Maximal independent families of sets (or of functions) Maximal orthogonal families of measures (mofs) Higher arity Hamel basis (basis of R over Q ) Maximal cofinitary groups (mcgs) This talk is about mofs, mcgs and Hamel bases. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 6 / 25

  10. Instances of maximal discrete sets Binary Transversals for equivalence relations Mad families Maximal eventually different families Maximal independent families of sets (or of functions) Maximal orthogonal families of measures (mofs) Higher arity Hamel basis (basis of R over Q ) Maximal cofinitary groups (mcgs) This talk is about mofs, mcgs and Hamel bases. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 6 / 25

  11. Instances of maximal discrete sets Binary Transversals for equivalence relations Mad families Maximal eventually different families Maximal independent families of sets (or of functions) Maximal orthogonal families of measures (mofs) Higher arity Hamel basis (basis of R over Q ) Maximal cofinitary groups (mcgs) This talk is about mofs, mcgs and Hamel bases. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 6 / 25

  12. Instances of maximal discrete sets Binary Transversals for equivalence relations Mad families Maximal eventually different families Maximal independent families of sets (or of functions) Maximal orthogonal families of measures (mofs) Higher arity Hamel basis (basis of R over Q ) Maximal cofinitary groups (mcgs) This talk is about mofs, mcgs and Hamel bases. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 6 / 25

  13. Interaction between different notions Existence of one type of irregular or maximal discrete set can entail the existence of another. If there is a projective Hamel basis, there is a projective Vitali set. “Every Σ 1 2 set is Lebesgue measurable” ⇒ “every Σ 1 2 set has the property of Baire” (Bartoszynsky 1984). More often, one can show no such interaction occurs: Theorem (Shelah 1984) “Every projective set has the property of Baire” �⇒ “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” Theorem (S.) “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” �⇒ “Every projective set has the property of Baire” Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 7 / 25

  14. Interaction between different notions Existence of one type of irregular or maximal discrete set can entail the existence of another. If there is a projective Hamel basis, there is a projective Vitali set. “Every Σ 1 2 set is Lebesgue measurable” ⇒ “every Σ 1 2 set has the property of Baire” (Bartoszynsky 1984). More often, one can show no such interaction occurs: Theorem (Shelah 1984) “Every projective set has the property of Baire” �⇒ “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” Theorem (S.) “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” �⇒ “Every projective set has the property of Baire” Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 7 / 25

  15. Interaction between different notions Existence of one type of irregular or maximal discrete set can entail the existence of another. If there is a projective Hamel basis, there is a projective Vitali set. “Every Σ 1 2 set is Lebesgue measurable” ⇒ “every Σ 1 2 set has the property of Baire” (Bartoszynsky 1984). More often, one can show no such interaction occurs: Theorem (Shelah 1984) “Every projective set has the property of Baire” �⇒ “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” Theorem (S.) “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” �⇒ “Every projective set has the property of Baire” Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 7 / 25

  16. Interaction between different notions Existence of one type of irregular or maximal discrete set can entail the existence of another. If there is a projective Hamel basis, there is a projective Vitali set. “Every Σ 1 2 set is Lebesgue measurable” ⇒ “every Σ 1 2 set has the property of Baire” (Bartoszynsky 1984). More often, one can show no such interaction occurs: Theorem (Shelah 1984) “Every projective set has the property of Baire” �⇒ “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” Theorem (S.) “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” �⇒ “Every projective set has the property of Baire” Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 7 / 25

  17. Interaction between different notions Existence of one type of irregular or maximal discrete set can entail the existence of another. If there is a projective Hamel basis, there is a projective Vitali set. “Every Σ 1 2 set is Lebesgue measurable” ⇒ “every Σ 1 2 set has the property of Baire” (Bartoszynsky 1984). More often, one can show no such interaction occurs: Theorem (Shelah 1984) “Every projective set has the property of Baire” �⇒ “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” Theorem (S.) “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” �⇒ “Every projective set has the property of Baire” Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 7 / 25

  18. Interaction between different notions Existence of one type of irregular or maximal discrete set can entail the existence of another. If there is a projective Hamel basis, there is a projective Vitali set. “Every Σ 1 2 set is Lebesgue measurable” ⇒ “every Σ 1 2 set has the property of Baire” (Bartoszynsky 1984). More often, one can show no such interaction occurs: Theorem (Shelah 1984) “Every projective set has the property of Baire” �⇒ “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” Theorem (S.) “Every projective set is Lebesgue measurable” �⇒ “Every projective set has the property of Baire” Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 7 / 25

  19. Outline Maximal discrete sets 1 Maximal cofinitary groups 2 Maximal orthogonal families of measures 3 Maximal discrete sets in the iterated Sacks extension 4 Hamel bases 5 Questions 6

  20. Cofinitary groups Work in the space X = S ∞ , the group of bijections from N to itself (permutations). id N is the identity function on N , the neutral element of S ∞ . Definition We say g ∈ S ∞ is cofinitary ⇐ ⇒ { n ∈ N | g ( n ) = n } is finite. G ≤ S ∞ is cofinitary ⇐ ⇒ every g ∈ G \ { id N } is cofinitary. A maximal cofinitary group is maximal R -discrete set, where ⇒ � g 0 , . . . , g n � S ∞ is not cofinitary. { g 0 , . . . , g n } ∈ R ⇐ Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 8 / 25

  21. Cofinitary groups Work in the space X = S ∞ , the group of bijections from N to itself (permutations). id N is the identity function on N , the neutral element of S ∞ . Definition We say g ∈ S ∞ is cofinitary ⇐ ⇒ { n ∈ N | g ( n ) = n } is finite. G ≤ S ∞ is cofinitary ⇐ ⇒ every g ∈ G \ { id N } is cofinitary. A maximal cofinitary group is maximal R -discrete set, where ⇒ � g 0 , . . . , g n � S ∞ is not cofinitary. { g 0 , . . . , g n } ∈ R ⇐ Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 8 / 25

  22. Cofinitary groups Work in the space X = S ∞ , the group of bijections from N to itself (permutations). id N is the identity function on N , the neutral element of S ∞ . Definition We say g ∈ S ∞ is cofinitary ⇐ ⇒ { n ∈ N | g ( n ) = n } is finite. G ≤ S ∞ is cofinitary ⇐ ⇒ every g ∈ G \ { id N } is cofinitary. A maximal cofinitary group is maximal R -discrete set, where ⇒ � g 0 , . . . , g n � S ∞ is not cofinitary. { g 0 , . . . , g n } ∈ R ⇐ Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 8 / 25

  23. Definability of mcgs Theorem (Kastermans) No mcg can be K σ . Some history: Gao-Zhang: If V = L , there is a mcg with a Π 1 1 set of generators. Kastermans: If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg. Theorem (Fischer-S.-Törnquist, 2015) If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg which remains maximal after adding any number of Cohen reals. Surprisingly, and in contrast to classical irregular sets: Theorem (Horowitz-Shelah, 2016) (ZF) There is a Borel maximal cofinitary group. By Σ 1 2 absoluteness, a Borel mcg remains maximal in any outer model. They also claim they will show there is a closed mcg in a future paper. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 9 / 25

  24. Definability of mcgs Theorem (Kastermans) No mcg can be K σ . Some history: Gao-Zhang: If V = L , there is a mcg with a Π 1 1 set of generators. Kastermans: If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg. Theorem (Fischer-S.-Törnquist, 2015) If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg which remains maximal after adding any number of Cohen reals. Surprisingly, and in contrast to classical irregular sets: Theorem (Horowitz-Shelah, 2016) (ZF) There is a Borel maximal cofinitary group. By Σ 1 2 absoluteness, a Borel mcg remains maximal in any outer model. They also claim they will show there is a closed mcg in a future paper. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 9 / 25

  25. Definability of mcgs Theorem (Kastermans) No mcg can be K σ . Some history: Gao-Zhang: If V = L , there is a mcg with a Π 1 1 set of generators. Kastermans: If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg. Theorem (Fischer-S.-Törnquist, 2015) If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg which remains maximal after adding any number of Cohen reals. Surprisingly, and in contrast to classical irregular sets: Theorem (Horowitz-Shelah, 2016) (ZF) There is a Borel maximal cofinitary group. By Σ 1 2 absoluteness, a Borel mcg remains maximal in any outer model. They also claim they will show there is a closed mcg in a future paper. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 9 / 25

  26. Definability of mcgs Theorem (Kastermans) No mcg can be K σ . Some history: Gao-Zhang: If V = L , there is a mcg with a Π 1 1 set of generators. Kastermans: If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg. Theorem (Fischer-S.-Törnquist, 2015) If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg which remains maximal after adding any number of Cohen reals. Surprisingly, and in contrast to classical irregular sets: Theorem (Horowitz-Shelah, 2016) (ZF) There is a Borel maximal cofinitary group. By Σ 1 2 absoluteness, a Borel mcg remains maximal in any outer model. They also claim they will show there is a closed mcg in a future paper. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 9 / 25

  27. Definability of mcgs Theorem (Kastermans) No mcg can be K σ . Some history: Gao-Zhang: If V = L , there is a mcg with a Π 1 1 set of generators. Kastermans: If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg. Theorem (Fischer-S.-Törnquist, 2015) If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg which remains maximal after adding any number of Cohen reals. Surprisingly, and in contrast to classical irregular sets: Theorem (Horowitz-Shelah, 2016) (ZF) There is a Borel maximal cofinitary group. By Σ 1 2 absoluteness, a Borel mcg remains maximal in any outer model. They also claim they will show there is a closed mcg in a future paper. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 9 / 25

  28. Definability of mcgs Theorem (Kastermans) No mcg can be K σ . Some history: Gao-Zhang: If V = L , there is a mcg with a Π 1 1 set of generators. Kastermans: If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg. Theorem (Fischer-S.-Törnquist, 2015) If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg which remains maximal after adding any number of Cohen reals. Surprisingly, and in contrast to classical irregular sets: Theorem (Horowitz-Shelah, 2016) (ZF) There is a Borel maximal cofinitary group. By Σ 1 2 absoluteness, a Borel mcg remains maximal in any outer model. They also claim they will show there is a closed mcg in a future paper. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 9 / 25

  29. Definability of mcgs Theorem (Kastermans) No mcg can be K σ . Some history: Gao-Zhang: If V = L , there is a mcg with a Π 1 1 set of generators. Kastermans: If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg. Theorem (Fischer-S.-Törnquist, 2015) If V = L , there is a Π 1 1 mcg which remains maximal after adding any number of Cohen reals. Surprisingly, and in contrast to classical irregular sets: Theorem (Horowitz-Shelah, 2016) (ZF) There is a Borel maximal cofinitary group. By Σ 1 2 absoluteness, a Borel mcg remains maximal in any outer model. They also claim they will show there is a closed mcg in a future paper. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 9 / 25

  30. Adding a generic cofinitary group Theorem (Zhang) Let G be a cofinitary group. There is a forcing P G which adds a generic permutation σ such that G ′ = �G , σ � is cofinitary, 1 G ′ is maximal with respect to the ground model: For any τ ∈ V \ G , 2 �G ′ , τ � is not cofinitary. We adapted this forcing so that given an arbitrary z ∈ 2 ω in addition, every new group element codes z : Theorem (Fischer-Törnquist-S. 2015) Let G be a cofinitary group and z ∈ 2 ω . There is a forcing P G , z which adds a generic permutation σ such that in addition to and above 1 2 z is computable from any x ∈ G ′ \ G . 3 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 10 / 25

  31. Adding a generic cofinitary group Theorem (Zhang) Let G be a cofinitary group. There is a forcing P G which adds a generic permutation σ such that G ′ = �G , σ � is cofinitary, 1 G ′ is maximal with respect to the ground model: For any τ ∈ V \ G , 2 �G ′ , τ � is not cofinitary. We adapted this forcing so that given an arbitrary z ∈ 2 ω in addition, every new group element codes z : Theorem (Fischer-Törnquist-S. 2015) Let G be a cofinitary group and z ∈ 2 ω . There is a forcing P G , z which adds a generic permutation σ such that in addition to and above 1 2 z is computable from any x ∈ G ′ \ G . 3 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 10 / 25

  32. Adding a generic cofinitary group Theorem (Zhang) Let G be a cofinitary group. There is a forcing P G which adds a generic permutation σ such that G ′ = �G , σ � is cofinitary, 1 G ′ is maximal with respect to the ground model: For any τ ∈ V \ G , 2 �G ′ , τ � is not cofinitary. We adapted this forcing so that given an arbitrary z ∈ 2 ω in addition, every new group element codes z : Theorem (Fischer-Törnquist-S. 2015) Let G be a cofinitary group and z ∈ 2 ω . There is a forcing P G , z which adds a generic permutation σ such that in addition to and above 1 2 z is computable from any x ∈ G ′ \ G . 3 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 10 / 25

  33. Adding a generic cofinitary group Theorem (Zhang) Let G be a cofinitary group. There is a forcing P G which adds a generic permutation σ such that G ′ = �G , σ � is cofinitary, 1 G ′ is maximal with respect to the ground model: For any τ ∈ V \ G , 2 �G ′ , τ � is not cofinitary. We adapted this forcing so that given an arbitrary z ∈ 2 ω in addition, every new group element codes z : Theorem (Fischer-Törnquist-S. 2015) Let G be a cofinitary group and z ∈ 2 ω . There is a forcing P G , z which adds a generic permutation σ such that in addition to and above 1 2 z is computable from any x ∈ G ′ \ G . 3 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 10 / 25

  34. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  35. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  36. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  37. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  38. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  39. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  40. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  41. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  42. A Cohen-indestructible Π 1 1 maximal cofinitary group The group is constructed by recursion, reproving Kasterman’s Theorem and imitating Miller’s classical construction of Π 1 1 mds . Assume we have { σ ν | ν < ξ } = G ξ where ξ < ω 1 . 1 Let η < ω 1 be least such that G ξ ∈ L η . 2 We may demand that moreover there is a surjection from ω onto 3 L η which is definable in L η . Use this to code L η canonically into a real z . 4 Let σ ξ be the ≤ L -least generic over L η for P G ξ , z . 5 The “natural” formula expressing membership in G = � ξ<ω 1 G ξ is Σ 1 resp. Σ 1 2 . It can be replaced by a Π 1 1 formula because each σ ∈ G knows via z a witness to the leading existential quantifier. Indesctructibility is shown using a “forcing product” lemma and the fact that Cohen forcing lies in each of the L η ’s. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 11 / 25

  43. Outline Maximal discrete sets 1 Maximal cofinitary groups 2 Maximal orthogonal families of measures 3 Maximal discrete sets in the iterated Sacks extension 4 Hamel bases 5 Questions 6

  44. Orthogonality of measures Let P ( 2 ω ) be the set of Borel probability measures on 2 ω . Note that P ( 2 ω ) is an effective Polish space. Two measures µ, ν ∈ P ( 2 ω ) are said to be orthogonal, written µ ⊥ ν exactly if there is a Borel set A ⊆ 2 ω such that µ ( A ) = 1 and ν ( A ) = 0 . This is an arithmetical relation. A maximal discrete set w.r.t. �⊥ is called a maximal orthogonal family of measures (or short, mof ). Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 12 / 25

  45. Orthogonality of measures Let P ( 2 ω ) be the set of Borel probability measures on 2 ω . Note that P ( 2 ω ) is an effective Polish space. Two measures µ, ν ∈ P ( 2 ω ) are said to be orthogonal, written µ ⊥ ν exactly if there is a Borel set A ⊆ 2 ω such that µ ( A ) = 1 and ν ( A ) = 0 . This is an arithmetical relation. A maximal discrete set w.r.t. �⊥ is called a maximal orthogonal family of measures (or short, mof ). Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 12 / 25

  46. Orthogonality of measures Let P ( 2 ω ) be the set of Borel probability measures on 2 ω . Note that P ( 2 ω ) is an effective Polish space. Two measures µ, ν ∈ P ( 2 ω ) are said to be orthogonal, written µ ⊥ ν exactly if there is a Borel set A ⊆ 2 ω such that µ ( A ) = 1 and ν ( A ) = 0 . This is an arithmetical relation. A maximal discrete set w.r.t. �⊥ is called a maximal orthogonal family of measures (or short, mof ). Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 12 / 25

  47. Orthogonality of measures Let P ( 2 ω ) be the set of Borel probability measures on 2 ω . Note that P ( 2 ω ) is an effective Polish space. Two measures µ, ν ∈ P ( 2 ω ) are said to be orthogonal, written µ ⊥ ν exactly if there is a Borel set A ⊆ 2 ω such that µ ( A ) = 1 and ν ( A ) = 0 . This is an arithmetical relation. A maximal discrete set w.r.t. �⊥ is called a maximal orthogonal family of measures (or short, mof ). Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 12 / 25

  48. Orthogonality of measures Let P ( 2 ω ) be the set of Borel probability measures on 2 ω . Note that P ( 2 ω ) is an effective Polish space. Two measures µ, ν ∈ P ( 2 ω ) are said to be orthogonal, written µ ⊥ ν exactly if there is a Borel set A ⊆ 2 ω such that µ ( A ) = 1 and ν ( A ) = 0 . This is an arithmetical relation. A maximal discrete set w.r.t. �⊥ is called a maximal orthogonal family of measures (or short, mof ). Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 12 / 25

  49. History of maximal orthogonal families Question (Mauldin, circa 1980) Can a mof in P ( 2 ω ) be analytic? The answer turned out to be ‘no’: Theorem (Preiss-Rataj, 1985) There is no analytic mof in P ( 2 ω ) . This is optimal, in a sense: Theorem (Fischer-Törnqust, 2009) In L , there is a Π 1 1 mof in P ( 2 ω ) . In fact: Theorem (S.-Törnquist 2015) If there is a Σ 1 2 mof in P ( 2 ω ) , there is a Π 1 1 mof . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 13 / 25

  50. History of maximal orthogonal families Question (Mauldin, circa 1980) Can a mof in P ( 2 ω ) be analytic? The answer turned out to be ‘no’: Theorem (Preiss-Rataj, 1985) There is no analytic mof in P ( 2 ω ) . This is optimal, in a sense: Theorem (Fischer-Törnqust, 2009) In L , there is a Π 1 1 mof in P ( 2 ω ) . In fact: Theorem (S.-Törnquist 2015) If there is a Σ 1 2 mof in P ( 2 ω ) , there is a Π 1 1 mof . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 13 / 25

  51. History of maximal orthogonal families Question (Mauldin, circa 1980) Can a mof in P ( 2 ω ) be analytic? The answer turned out to be ‘no’: Theorem (Preiss-Rataj, 1985) There is no analytic mof in P ( 2 ω ) . This is optimal, in a sense: Theorem (Fischer-Törnqust, 2009) In L , there is a Π 1 1 mof in P ( 2 ω ) . In fact: Theorem (S.-Törnquist 2015) If there is a Σ 1 2 mof in P ( 2 ω ) , there is a Π 1 1 mof . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 13 / 25

  52. History of maximal orthogonal families Question (Mauldin, circa 1980) Can a mof in P ( 2 ω ) be analytic? The answer turned out to be ‘no’: Theorem (Preiss-Rataj, 1985) There is no analytic mof in P ( 2 ω ) . This is optimal, in a sense: Theorem (Fischer-Törnqust, 2009) In L , there is a Π 1 1 mof in P ( 2 ω ) . In fact: Theorem (S.-Törnquist 2015) If there is a Σ 1 2 mof in P ( 2 ω ) , there is a Π 1 1 mof . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 13 / 25

  53. Can definable mofs survive forcing? Mofs are fragile creatures: Adding any real destroys maximality of mofs from the 1 groundmodel (observed by Ben Miller; not restricted to forcing extensions) Using methods reminiscent of Hjorth’s theory of turbulency, one 2 can show there is no Σ 1 2 mof whenever there exists a real of the following type over L : ◮ A Cohen real (Fischer-Törnquist, 2009) ◮ A random real (Fischer-Friedman-Törnquist, 2010). ◮ A Mathias real (S.-Törnquist, 2015). Question (Fischer-Törnquist) If there is a Π 1 1 mof , does it follow that P ( ω ) ⊆ L ? Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 14 / 25

  54. Can definable mofs survive forcing? Mofs are fragile creatures: Adding any real destroys maximality of mofs from the 1 groundmodel (observed by Ben Miller; not restricted to forcing extensions) Using methods reminiscent of Hjorth’s theory of turbulency, one 2 can show there is no Σ 1 2 mof whenever there exists a real of the following type over L : ◮ A Cohen real (Fischer-Törnquist, 2009) ◮ A random real (Fischer-Friedman-Törnquist, 2010). ◮ A Mathias real (S.-Törnquist, 2015). Question (Fischer-Törnquist) If there is a Π 1 1 mof , does it follow that P ( ω ) ⊆ L ? Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 14 / 25

  55. Can definable mofs survive forcing? Mofs are fragile creatures: Adding any real destroys maximality of mofs from the 1 groundmodel (observed by Ben Miller; not restricted to forcing extensions) Using methods reminiscent of Hjorth’s theory of turbulency, one 2 can show there is no Σ 1 2 mof whenever there exists a real of the following type over L : ◮ A Cohen real (Fischer-Törnquist, 2009) ◮ A random real (Fischer-Friedman-Törnquist, 2010). ◮ A Mathias real (S.-Törnquist, 2015). Question (Fischer-Törnquist) If there is a Π 1 1 mof , does it follow that P ( ω ) ⊆ L ? Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 14 / 25

  56. Can definable mofs survive forcing? Mofs are fragile creatures: Adding any real destroys maximality of mofs from the 1 groundmodel (observed by Ben Miller; not restricted to forcing extensions) Using methods reminiscent of Hjorth’s theory of turbulency, one 2 can show there is no Σ 1 2 mof whenever there exists a real of the following type over L : ◮ A Cohen real (Fischer-Törnquist, 2009) ◮ A random real (Fischer-Friedman-Törnquist, 2010). ◮ A Mathias real (S.-Törnquist, 2015). Question (Fischer-Törnquist) If there is a Π 1 1 mof , does it follow that P ( ω ) ⊆ L ? Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 14 / 25

  57. Can definable mofs survive forcing? Mofs are fragile creatures: Adding any real destroys maximality of mofs from the 1 groundmodel (observed by Ben Miller; not restricted to forcing extensions) Using methods reminiscent of Hjorth’s theory of turbulency, one 2 can show there is no Σ 1 2 mof whenever there exists a real of the following type over L : ◮ A Cohen real (Fischer-Törnquist, 2009) ◮ A random real (Fischer-Friedman-Törnquist, 2010). ◮ A Mathias real (S.-Törnquist, 2015). Question (Fischer-Törnquist) If there is a Π 1 1 mof , does it follow that P ( ω ) ⊆ L ? Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 14 / 25

  58. Can definable mofs survive forcing? Mofs are fragile creatures: Adding any real destroys maximality of mofs from the 1 groundmodel (observed by Ben Miller; not restricted to forcing extensions) Using methods reminiscent of Hjorth’s theory of turbulency, one 2 can show there is no Σ 1 2 mof whenever there exists a real of the following type over L : ◮ A Cohen real (Fischer-Törnquist, 2009) ◮ A random real (Fischer-Friedman-Törnquist, 2010). ◮ A Mathias real (S.-Törnquist, 2015). Question (Fischer-Törnquist) If there is a Π 1 1 mof , does it follow that P ( ω ) ⊆ L ? Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 14 / 25

  59. Outline Maximal discrete sets 1 Maximal cofinitary groups 2 Maximal orthogonal families of measures 3 Maximal discrete sets in the iterated Sacks extension 4 Hamel bases 5 Questions 6

  60. A general theorem for Σ 1 1 relations Theorem (S. 2016) Let R be a binary symmetric Σ 1 1 relation on an effective Polish space X. If ¯ s is generic for iterated Sacks forcing over L , there is a ∆ 1 2 R- mds in L [¯ s ] . Note we are always referring to the lightface (effective) hierarchy. As existence of a Σ 1 2 mof implies existence of a Π 1 1 mof , we obtain a strong negative answer to the previous question: Theorem (S. 2016) 1 mof ’ is consistent with 2 ω = ω 2 . The statement ‘there is a Π 1 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 15 / 25

  61. A general theorem for Σ 1 1 relations Theorem (S. 2016) Let R be a binary symmetric Σ 1 1 relation on an effective Polish space X. If ¯ s is generic for iterated Sacks forcing over L , there is a ∆ 1 2 R- mds in L [¯ s ] . Note we are always referring to the lightface (effective) hierarchy. As existence of a Σ 1 2 mof implies existence of a Π 1 1 mof , we obtain a strong negative answer to the previous question: Theorem (S. 2016) 1 mof ’ is consistent with 2 ω = ω 2 . The statement ‘there is a Π 1 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 15 / 25

  62. A general theorem for Σ 1 1 relations Theorem (S. 2016) Let R be a binary symmetric Σ 1 1 relation on an effective Polish space X. If ¯ s is generic for iterated Sacks forcing over L , there is a ∆ 1 2 R- mds in L [¯ s ] . Note we are always referring to the lightface (effective) hierarchy. As existence of a Σ 1 2 mof implies existence of a Π 1 1 mof , we obtain a strong negative answer to the previous question: Theorem (S. 2016) 1 mof ’ is consistent with 2 ω = ω 2 . The statement ‘there is a Π 1 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 15 / 25

  63. A general theorem for Σ 1 1 relations Theorem (S. 2016) Let R be a binary symmetric Σ 1 1 relation on an effective Polish space X. If ¯ s is generic for iterated Sacks forcing over L , there is a ∆ 1 2 R- mds in L [¯ s ] . Note we are always referring to the lightface (effective) hierarchy. As existence of a Σ 1 2 mof implies existence of a Π 1 1 mof , we obtain a strong negative answer to the previous question: Theorem (S. 2016) 1 mof ’ is consistent with 2 ω = ω 2 . The statement ‘there is a Π 1 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 15 / 25

  64. Proof sketch (for a single Sacks real and Borel R ). 1 relation on ω ω and L [ s ] is a Sacks Assume R is a symmetric ∆ 1 extension of L . Recall that Sacks forcing S is the set of perfect trees p ⊆ 2 <ω , ordered by inclusion and [ p ] is the set of branches through p . We need the following standard fact: Fact Any element of L [ s ] ∩ ω ω is equal to f ( s ) for some continuous function f : 2 ω → ω ω with code in L . We also need the following theorem of Galvin: Theorem (Galvin’s Theorem) Let c : ( 2 ω ) 2 → { 0 , 1 } be symmetric and Baire measurable. Then there is a perfect set P ⊆ 2 ω such that c is constant on P 2 \ diag . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 16 / 25

  65. Proof sketch (for a single Sacks real and Borel R ). 1 relation on ω ω and L [ s ] is a Sacks Assume R is a symmetric ∆ 1 extension of L . Recall that Sacks forcing S is the set of perfect trees p ⊆ 2 <ω , ordered by inclusion and [ p ] is the set of branches through p . We need the following standard fact: Fact Any element of L [ s ] ∩ ω ω is equal to f ( s ) for some continuous function f : 2 ω → ω ω with code in L . We also need the following theorem of Galvin: Theorem (Galvin’s Theorem) Let c : ( 2 ω ) 2 → { 0 , 1 } be symmetric and Baire measurable. Then there is a perfect set P ⊆ 2 ω such that c is constant on P 2 \ diag . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 16 / 25

  66. Proof sketch (for a single Sacks real and Borel R ). 1 relation on ω ω and L [ s ] is a Sacks Assume R is a symmetric ∆ 1 extension of L . Recall that Sacks forcing S is the set of perfect trees p ⊆ 2 <ω , ordered by inclusion and [ p ] is the set of branches through p . We need the following standard fact: Fact Any element of L [ s ] ∩ ω ω is equal to f ( s ) for some continuous function f : 2 ω → ω ω with code in L . We also need the following theorem of Galvin: Theorem (Galvin’s Theorem) Let c : ( 2 ω ) 2 → { 0 , 1 } be symmetric and Baire measurable. Then there is a perfect set P ⊆ 2 ω such that c is constant on P 2 \ diag . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 16 / 25

  67. Proof sketch (for a single Sacks real and Borel R ). 1 relation on ω ω and L [ s ] is a Sacks Assume R is a symmetric ∆ 1 extension of L . Recall that Sacks forcing S is the set of perfect trees p ⊆ 2 <ω , ordered by inclusion and [ p ] is the set of branches through p . We need the following standard fact: Fact Any element of L [ s ] ∩ ω ω is equal to f ( s ) for some continuous function f : 2 ω → ω ω with code in L . We also need the following theorem of Galvin: Theorem (Galvin’s Theorem) Let c : ( 2 ω ) 2 → { 0 , 1 } be symmetric and Baire measurable. Then there is a perfect set P ⊆ 2 ω such that c is constant on P 2 \ diag . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 16 / 25

  68. Proof sketch (for a single Sacks real and Borel R ). 1 relation on ω ω and L [ s ] is a Sacks Assume R is a symmetric ∆ 1 extension of L . Recall that Sacks forcing S is the set of perfect trees p ⊆ 2 <ω , ordered by inclusion and [ p ] is the set of branches through p . We need the following standard fact: Fact Any element of L [ s ] ∩ ω ω is equal to f ( s ) for some continuous function f : 2 ω → ω ω with code in L . We also need the following theorem of Galvin: Theorem (Galvin’s Theorem) Let c : ( 2 ω ) 2 → { 0 , 1 } be symmetric and Baire measurable. Then there is a perfect set P ⊆ 2 ω such that c is constant on P 2 \ diag . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 16 / 25

  69. Proof sketch (for a single Sacks real and Borel R ). 1 relation on ω ω and L [ s ] is a Sacks Assume R is a symmetric ∆ 1 extension of L . Recall that Sacks forcing S is the set of perfect trees p ⊆ 2 <ω , ordered by inclusion and [ p ] is the set of branches through p . We need the following standard fact: Fact Any element of L [ s ] ∩ ω ω is equal to f ( s ) for some continuous function f : 2 ω → ω ω with code in L . We also need the following theorem of Galvin: Theorem (Galvin’s Theorem) Let c : ( 2 ω ) 2 → { 0 , 1 } be symmetric and Baire measurable. Then there is a perfect set P ⊆ 2 ω such that c is constant on P 2 \ diag . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 16 / 25

  70. A lemma: Complete and discrete conditions Lemma Suppose R is a Σ 1 1 symmetric binary relation on ω ω , p ∈ S , and f ∈ C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . There is q ≤ p such that one of the following holds: f ′′ [ q ] is R-discrete 1 f ′′ [ q ] is R-complete, i.e. any two elements of f ′′ [ q ] are R-related. 2 Proof. Apply Galvin’s Theorem for the coloring on [ p ] 2 given by � 1 if f ( x ) R f ( y ) , c ( x , y ) = if f ( x ) � � 0 R f ( y ) . is a Π 1 Note: 1 statement about q ; 1 is a Π 1 2 statement about q , so both are absolute. 2 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 17 / 25

  71. A lemma: Complete and discrete conditions Lemma Suppose R is a Σ 1 1 symmetric binary relation on ω ω , p ∈ S , and f ∈ C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . There is q ≤ p such that one of the following holds: f ′′ [ q ] is R-discrete 1 f ′′ [ q ] is R-complete, i.e. any two elements of f ′′ [ q ] are R-related. 2 Proof. Apply Galvin’s Theorem for the coloring on [ p ] 2 given by � 1 if f ( x ) R f ( y ) , c ( x , y ) = if f ( x ) � � 0 R f ( y ) . is a Π 1 Note: 1 statement about q ; 1 is a Π 1 2 statement about q , so both are absolute. 2 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 17 / 25

  72. A lemma: Complete and discrete conditions Lemma Suppose R is a Σ 1 1 symmetric binary relation on ω ω , p ∈ S , and f ∈ C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . There is q ≤ p such that one of the following holds: f ′′ [ q ] is R-discrete 1 f ′′ [ q ] is R-complete, i.e. any two elements of f ′′ [ q ] are R-related. 2 Proof. Apply Galvin’s Theorem for the coloring on [ p ] 2 given by � 1 if f ( x ) R f ( y ) , c ( x , y ) = if f ( x ) � � 0 R f ( y ) . is a Π 1 Note: 1 statement about q ; 1 is a Π 1 2 statement about q , so both are absolute. 2 Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 17 / 25

  73. Ideas for the proof (continued). We also use the following well-known property of Sacks forcing, which can be seen as a special case of the previous: Corollary Say Φ is a Σ 1 1 (or Π 1 1 ) formula, p ∈ S and p � ¬ Φ(˙ s ) . Then there is q ≤ p such that [ q ] ∩ { x | Φ( x ) } = ∅ . Also note that [ q ] ∩ { x | Φ( x ) } = ∅ is Π 1 1 , hence absolute, and thus will also hold in the Sacks extension. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 18 / 25

  74. Ideas for the proof (continued). We also use the following well-known property of Sacks forcing, which can be seen as a special case of the previous: Corollary Say Φ is a Σ 1 1 (or Π 1 1 ) formula, p ∈ S and p � ¬ Φ(˙ s ) . Then there is q ≤ p such that [ q ] ∩ { x | Φ( x ) } = ∅ . Also note that [ q ] ∩ { x | Φ( x ) } = ∅ is Π 1 1 , hence absolute, and thus will also hold in the Sacks extension. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 18 / 25

  75. Ideas for the proof (continued). We also use the following well-known property of Sacks forcing, which can be seen as a special case of the previous: Corollary Say Φ is a Σ 1 1 (or Π 1 1 ) formula, p ∈ S and p � ¬ Φ(˙ s ) . Then there is q ≤ p such that [ q ] ∩ { x | Φ( x ) } = ∅ . Also note that [ q ] ∩ { x | Φ( x ) } = ∅ is Π 1 1 , hence absolute, and thus will also hold in the Sacks extension. Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 18 / 25

  76. Work in L . Let � ( p ξ , f ξ ) | ξ < ω 1 � enumerate S × C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . By recursion, choose for each ξ < ω 1 a tree T ξ ⊆ p ξ such that in L [ s ] , A = � { [ T ξ ] | ξ < ω 1 } will be a mds . At stage ξ < ω 1 , suppose � � � p ξ � f ξ (˙ s ) / ∈ span R [ T ν ] , (1) ν<ξ otherwise let T ξ = ∅ . By the previous, we may find q ≤ p ξ such that ′′ [ q ] is R -discrete or R -complete. f ξ 1 � � � ′′ [ q ] ∩ span R = ∅ . f ξ ν<ξ [ T ξ ] 2 ′′ [ q ] . In discrete case, let [ T ξ ] = f ξ In complete case, let [ T ξ ] = { f ξ ( x ) } where x is the left-most branch of q . By construction A is ∆ 1 2 and discrete in L [ s ] . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 19 / 25

  77. Work in L . Let � ( p ξ , f ξ ) | ξ < ω 1 � enumerate S × C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . By recursion, choose for each ξ < ω 1 a tree T ξ ⊆ p ξ such that in L [ s ] , A = � { [ T ξ ] | ξ < ω 1 } will be a mds . At stage ξ < ω 1 , suppose � � � p ξ � f ξ (˙ s ) / ∈ span R [ T ν ] , (1) ν<ξ otherwise let T ξ = ∅ . By the previous, we may find q ≤ p ξ such that ′′ [ q ] is R -discrete or R -complete. f ξ 1 � � � ′′ [ q ] ∩ span R = ∅ . f ξ ν<ξ [ T ξ ] 2 ′′ [ q ] . In discrete case, let [ T ξ ] = f ξ In complete case, let [ T ξ ] = { f ξ ( x ) } where x is the left-most branch of q . By construction A is ∆ 1 2 and discrete in L [ s ] . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 19 / 25

  78. Work in L . Let � ( p ξ , f ξ ) | ξ < ω 1 � enumerate S × C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . By recursion, choose for each ξ < ω 1 a tree T ξ ⊆ p ξ such that in L [ s ] , A = � { [ T ξ ] | ξ < ω 1 } will be a mds . At stage ξ < ω 1 , suppose � � � p ξ � f ξ (˙ s ) / ∈ span R [ T ν ] , (1) ν<ξ otherwise let T ξ = ∅ . By the previous, we may find q ≤ p ξ such that ′′ [ q ] is R -discrete or R -complete. f ξ 1 � � � ′′ [ q ] ∩ span R = ∅ . f ξ ν<ξ [ T ξ ] 2 ′′ [ q ] . In discrete case, let [ T ξ ] = f ξ In complete case, let [ T ξ ] = { f ξ ( x ) } where x is the left-most branch of q . By construction A is ∆ 1 2 and discrete in L [ s ] . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 19 / 25

  79. Work in L . Let � ( p ξ , f ξ ) | ξ < ω 1 � enumerate S × C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . By recursion, choose for each ξ < ω 1 a tree T ξ ⊆ p ξ such that in L [ s ] , A = � { [ T ξ ] | ξ < ω 1 } will be a mds . At stage ξ < ω 1 , suppose � � � p ξ � f ξ (˙ s ) / ∈ span R [ T ν ] , (1) ν<ξ otherwise let T ξ = ∅ . By the previous, we may find q ≤ p ξ such that ′′ [ q ] is R -discrete or R -complete. f ξ 1 � � � ′′ [ q ] ∩ span R = ∅ . f ξ ν<ξ [ T ξ ] 2 ′′ [ q ] . In discrete case, let [ T ξ ] = f ξ In complete case, let [ T ξ ] = { f ξ ( x ) } where x is the left-most branch of q . By construction A is ∆ 1 2 and discrete in L [ s ] . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 19 / 25

  80. Work in L . Let � ( p ξ , f ξ ) | ξ < ω 1 � enumerate S × C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . By recursion, choose for each ξ < ω 1 a tree T ξ ⊆ p ξ such that in L [ s ] , A = � { [ T ξ ] | ξ < ω 1 } will be a mds . At stage ξ < ω 1 , suppose � � � p ξ � f ξ (˙ s ) / ∈ span R [ T ν ] , (1) ν<ξ otherwise let T ξ = ∅ . By the previous, we may find q ≤ p ξ such that ′′ [ q ] is R -discrete or R -complete. f ξ 1 � � � ′′ [ q ] ∩ span R = ∅ . f ξ ν<ξ [ T ξ ] 2 ′′ [ q ] . In discrete case, let [ T ξ ] = f ξ In complete case, let [ T ξ ] = { f ξ ( x ) } where x is the left-most branch of q . By construction A is ∆ 1 2 and discrete in L [ s ] . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 19 / 25

  81. Work in L . Let � ( p ξ , f ξ ) | ξ < ω 1 � enumerate S × C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . By recursion, choose for each ξ < ω 1 a tree T ξ ⊆ p ξ such that in L [ s ] , A = � { [ T ξ ] | ξ < ω 1 } will be a mds . At stage ξ < ω 1 , suppose � � � p ξ � f ξ (˙ s ) / ∈ span R [ T ν ] , (1) ν<ξ otherwise let T ξ = ∅ . By the previous, we may find q ≤ p ξ such that ′′ [ q ] is R -discrete or R -complete. f ξ 1 � � � ′′ [ q ] ∩ span R = ∅ . f ξ ν<ξ [ T ξ ] 2 ′′ [ q ] . In discrete case, let [ T ξ ] = f ξ In complete case, let [ T ξ ] = { f ξ ( x ) } where x is the left-most branch of q . By construction A is ∆ 1 2 and discrete in L [ s ] . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 19 / 25

  82. Work in L . Let � ( p ξ , f ξ ) | ξ < ω 1 � enumerate S × C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . By recursion, choose for each ξ < ω 1 a tree T ξ ⊆ p ξ such that in L [ s ] , A = � { [ T ξ ] | ξ < ω 1 } will be a mds . At stage ξ < ω 1 , suppose � � � p ξ � f ξ (˙ s ) / ∈ span R [ T ν ] , (1) ν<ξ otherwise let T ξ = ∅ . By the previous, we may find q ≤ p ξ such that ′′ [ q ] is R -discrete or R -complete. f ξ 1 � � � ′′ [ q ] ∩ span R = ∅ . f ξ ν<ξ [ T ξ ] 2 ′′ [ q ] . In discrete case, let [ T ξ ] = f ξ In complete case, let [ T ξ ] = { f ξ ( x ) } where x is the left-most branch of q . By construction A is ∆ 1 2 and discrete in L [ s ] . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 19 / 25

  83. Work in L . Let � ( p ξ , f ξ ) | ξ < ω 1 � enumerate S × C ( 2 ω , ω ω ) . By recursion, choose for each ξ < ω 1 a tree T ξ ⊆ p ξ such that in L [ s ] , A = � { [ T ξ ] | ξ < ω 1 } will be a mds . At stage ξ < ω 1 , suppose � � � p ξ � f ξ (˙ s ) / ∈ span R [ T ν ] , (1) ν<ξ otherwise let T ξ = ∅ . By the previous, we may find q ≤ p ξ such that ′′ [ q ] is R -discrete or R -complete. f ξ 1 � � � ′′ [ q ] ∩ span R = ∅ . f ξ ν<ξ [ T ξ ] 2 ′′ [ q ] . In discrete case, let [ T ξ ] = f ξ In complete case, let [ T ξ ] = { f ξ ( x ) } where x is the left-most branch of q . By construction A is ∆ 1 2 and discrete in L [ s ] . Schrittesser (Copenhagen) Definability of maximal discrete sets Arctic Set Theory 3 19 / 25

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend