coherence under uncertainty philosophical and
play

Coherence under uncertainty: Philosophical and psychological - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Coherence under uncertainty: Philosophical and psychological applications Niki Pfeifer 1 Giuseppe Sanfilippo 2 Angelo Gilio 3 1 Ludwig-Maximilians-University Munich, Germany 2 Department of Mathematics and Computer Science University of Palermo,


  1. Example: Probabilistic modus ponens (e.g., Hailperin, 1996; Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2006) Modus ponens Probabilistic modus ponens (Conditional event) (Material conditional) p ( C ∣ A ) = . 90 p ( A ⊃ C ) = . 90 If A , then C p ( A ) = . 50 p ( A ) = . 50 A . 45 ≤ p ( C ) ≤ . 95 . 40 ≤ p ( C ) ≤ . 90 C xy ≤ p ( C ) ≤ xy + 1 − x max { 0 , x + y − 1 } ≤ p ( C ) ≤ x . . . where the consequence relation (“———”) is deductive.

  2. Modus ponens as a special case of Cut p ( B ∣ A ) = x Cut (Gilio, 2002) : p ( C ∣ A ∧ B ) = y xy ≤ p ( C ∣ A ) ≤ xy + 1 − x Modus ponens:

  3. Modus ponens as a special case of Cut p ( B ∣ A ) = x Cut (Gilio, 2002) : p ( C ∣ A ∧ B ) = y xy ≤ p ( C ∣ A ) ≤ xy + 1 − x Modus ponens: Let A ≡ ⊺ , then Since p ( E ) = def p ( E ∣ ⊺ ) and p ( E ∧ ⊺ ) = p ( E ) , we obtain: p ( B ∣ ⊺ ) = x Modus ponens: p ( C ∣ ⊺∧ B ) = y Cut (Gilio, 2002) : xy ≤ p ( C ∣ ⊺ ) ≤ xy + 1 − x

  4. Modus ponens as a special case of Cut p ( B ∣ A ) = x Cut (Gilio, 2002) : p ( C ∣ A ∧ B ) = y xy ≤ p ( C ∣ A ) ≤ xy + 1 − x Modus ponens: Let A ≡ ⊺ . Since p ( E ) = def p ( E ∣ ⊺ ) and p ( E ∧ ⊺ ) = p ( E ) , we obtain: p ( B ∣ ⊺ ) = x Modus ponens: p ( C ∣ ⊺∧ B ) = y Cut (Gilio, 2002) : xy ≤ p ( C ∣ ⊺ ) ≤ xy + 1 − x

  5. Modus tollens vs. Contraposition Consider if A, then B. Will not-A, if not-B?

  6. Modus tollens vs. Contraposition Consider if A, then B. Will not-A, if not-B? P1 If A , then B If A , then B P1 not- B P2 C If not- B , then not- A not- A C

  7. Modus tollens vs. Contraposition Consider if A, then B. Will not-A, if not-B? P1 If A , then B If A , then B P1 not- B P2 C If not- B , then not- A not- A C P ( B ∣ A ) = x , P ( ¬ B ) = y ⊧ 0 ≤ θ ≤ P ( ¬ A ) ≤ 1

  8. Modus tollens vs. Contraposition Consider if A, then B. Will not-A, if not-B? P1 If A , then B If A , then B P1 not- B P2 C If not- B , then not- A not- A C P ( B ∣ A ) = x , P ( ¬ B ) = y P ( B ∣ A ) = x ⊧ 0 ≤ θ ≤ P ( ¬ A ) ≤ 1 ⊧ 0 ≤ P ( ¬ A ∣ ¬ B ) ≤ 1

  9. Modus tollens vs. Contraposition Consider if A, then B. Will not-A, if not-B? P1 If A , then B If A , then B P1 not- B P2 C If not- B , then not- A not- A C P ( B ∣ A ) = x , P ( ¬ B ) = y P ( B ∣ A ) = x ⊧ 0 ≤ θ ≤ P ( ¬ A ) ≤ 1 ⊧ 0 ≤ P ( ¬ A ∣ ¬ B ) ≤ 1 the probabilistic modus tollens the probabilistic contraposition is probabilistically informative is probabilistically non-informative i.e., x and y constrain P (¬ A ) i.e., the tightest coherent probability bounds are 0 and 1

  10. Modus tollens vs. Contraposition Consider if A, then B. Will not-A, if not-B? P1 If A , then B If A , then B P1 not- B P2 C If not- B , then not- A not- A C P ( B ∣ A ) = x , P ( ¬ B ) = y P ( B ∣ A ) = x ⊧ 0 ≤ P ( ¬ A ∣ ¬ B ) ≤ 1 ≤ P ( ¬ A ) ≤ 1 ⊧ 0 ≤ θ the probabilistic modus tollens the probabilistic contraposition is probabilistically informative is probabilistically non-informative i.e., x and y constrain P (¬ A ) i.e., the tightest coherent probability bounds are 0 and 1 θ = 1 − x − y if x + y ≤ 1, 1 − x θ = x + y − 1 if x + y > 1, x

  11. Sample paradoxes of the material conditional (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) B Not: A If A , then B If A , then B

  12. Sample paradoxes of the material conditional (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) B Not: A If A , then B If A , then B (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) B ¬ A A ⊃ B A ⊃ B

  13. Sample paradoxes of the material conditional (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) P ( B ) = x P ( ¬ A ) = x x ≤ P ( A ⊃ B ) ≤ 1 x ≤ P ( A ⊃ B ) ≤ 1 probabilistically informative

  14. Sample paradoxes of the material conditional (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) P ( B ) = x P ( ¬ A ) = x x ≤ P ( A ⊃ B ) ≤ 1 x ≤ P ( A ⊃ B ) ≤ 1 probabilistically informative

  15. Sample paradoxes of the material conditional (Pfeifer, 2014, Studia Logica ) Paradoxes of the material conditional, e.g., (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) P ( B ) = x P ( ¬ A ) = x 0 ≤ P ( B ∣ A ) ≤ 1 0 ≤ P ( B ∣ A ) ≤ 1 probabilistically non-informative

  16. Sample paradoxes of the material conditional (Pfeifer, 2014, Studia Logica ) Paradoxes of the material conditional, e.g., (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) P ( B ) = x P ( ¬ A ) = x 0 ≤ P ( B ∣ A ) ≤ 1 0 ≤ P ( B ∣ A ) ≤ 1 probabilistically non-informative This matches the data (Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2011) .

  17. Sample paradoxes of the material conditional (Pfeifer, 2014, Studia Logica ) Paradoxes of the material conditional, e.g., (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) P ( B ) = x P ( ¬ A ) = x 0 ≤ P ( B ∣ A ) ≤ 1 0 ≤ P ( B ∣ A ) ≤ 1 probabilistically non-informative This matches the data (Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2011) . Paradox 1: Special case covered in the coherence approach, but not covered in the standard approach to probability: If P ( B ) = 1, then P ( A ∧ B ) = P ( A ) .

  18. Sample paradoxes of the material conditional (Pfeifer, 2014, Studia Logica ) Paradoxes of the material conditional, e.g., (Paradox 1) (Paradox 2) P ( B ) = x P ( ¬ A ) = x 0 ≤ P ( B ∣ A ) ≤ 1 0 ≤ P ( B ∣ A ) ≤ 1 probabilistically non-informative This matches the data (Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2011) . Paradox 1: Special case covered in the coherence approach, but not covered in the standard approach to probability: If P ( B ) = 1, then P ( A ∧ B ) = P ( A ) . Thus, P ( B ∣ A ) = P ( A ∧ B ) P ( A ) = 1, if P ( A ) > 0. = P ( A ) P ( A )

  19. Inf. vers. of t. paradoxes (Pfeifer (2014). Studia Logica ; Pfeifer and Douven (2014). R ev. Phil. Psy.) From Pr ( B ) = 1 and A ∧ B ≡ � infer Pr ( B ∣ A ) = 0 is coherent.

  20. Inf. vers. of t. paradoxes (Pfeifer (2014). Studia Logica ; Pfeifer and Douven (2014). R ev. Phil. Psy.) From Pr ( B ) = 1 and A ∧ B ≡ � infer Pr ( B ∣ A ) = 0 is coherent. From Pr ( B ) = 1 and A ⊃ B ≡ ⊺ infer Pr ( B ∣ A ) = 1 is coherent.

  21. Inf. vers. of t. paradoxes (Pfeifer (2014). Studia Logica ; Pfeifer and Douven (2014). R ev. Phil. Psy.) From Pr ( B ) = 1 and A ∧ B ≡ � infer Pr ( B ∣ A ) = 0 is coherent. From Pr ( B ) = 1 and A ⊃ B ≡ ⊺ infer Pr ( B ∣ A ) = 1 is coherent. From Pr ( B ) = x and Pr ( A ) = y > 0 infer max { 0 , x + y − 1 } ⩽ Pr ( B ∣ A ) ⩽ min { x y , 1 } is coherent. y

  22. Inf. vers. of t. paradoxes (Pfeifer (2014). Studia Logica ; Pfeifer and Douven (2014). R ev. Phil. Psy.) From Pr ( B ) = 1 and A ∧ B ≡ � infer Pr ( B ∣ A ) = 0 is coherent. From Pr ( B ) = 1 and A ⊃ B ≡ ⊺ infer Pr ( B ∣ A ) = 1 is coherent. From Pr ( B ) = x and Pr ( A ) = y > 0 infer max { 0 , x + y − 1 } ⩽ Pr ( B ∣ A ) ⩽ min { x y , 1 } is coherent. y . . . a special case of the cautious monotonicity rule of System P (Gilio, 2002) .

  23. Table of contents Introduction Interaction of formal/normative and empirical work Mental probability logic Conditionals under coherence Modus ponens and Modus tollens Paradoxes Probabilistic syllogisms (joint work with Gilio & Sanfilippo) A note on Chater & Oaksford’s probabilistic syllogisms The coherence perspective on syllogisms Concluding remarks References Appendix

  24. Aristotelian Syllogisms ▸ Long history in psychology (starting with St¨ orring (1908))

  25. Aristotelian Syllogisms ▸ Long history in psychology (starting with St¨ orring (1908)) ▸ Aristotelian syllogisms: ▸ either too strict (universal, ∀ ) or too weak (existential, ∃ ) quantifiers ▸ not a language for uncertainty / vagueness

  26. Aristotelian Syllogisms ▸ Long history in psychology (starting with St¨ orring (1908)) ▸ Aristotelian syllogisms: ▸ either too strict (universal, ∀ ) or too weak (existential, ∃ ) quantifiers ▸ not a language for uncertainty / vagueness ▸ Developing coherence based probability logic semantics for Aristotelian syllogisms

  27. Syllogistic types of propositions and figures (see, e.g. Pfeifer, 2006a) Name of Proposition Type PL formula ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ Px ) ∧ ∃ xSx Universal affirmative (A) ∃ x ( Sx ∧ Px ) Particular affirmative (I) ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ ¬ Px ) ∧ ∃ xSx Universal negative (E) ∃ x ( Sx ∧ ¬ Px ) Particular negative (O)

  28. Syllogistic types of propositions and figures (see, e.g. Pfeifer, 2006a) Name of Proposition Type PL formula ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ Px ) ∧ ∃ xSx Universal affirmative (A) ∃ x ( Sx ∧ Px ) Particular affirmative (I) ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ ¬ Px ) ∧ ∃ xSx Universal negative (E) ∃ x ( Sx ∧ ¬ Px ) Particular negative (O) Figure name 1 2 3 4 Premise 1 MP PM MP PM Premise 2 SM SM MS MS Conclusion SP SP SP SP

  29. Syllogistic types of propositions and figures (see, e.g. Pfeifer, 2006a) Name of Proposition Type PL formula ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ Px ) ∧ ∃ xSx Universal affirmative (A) ∃ x ( Sx ∧ Px ) Particular affirmative (I) ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ ¬ Px ) ∧ ∃ xSx Universal negative (E) ∃ x ( Sx ∧ ¬ Px ) Particular negative (O) Figure name 1 2 3 4 Premise 1 MP PM MP PM Premise 2 SM SM MS MS Conclusion SP SP SP SP 256 possible syllogisms, 24 Aristotelianly-valid, 9 require ∃ xSx

  30. Traditionally valid syllogisms (see, e.g., Pfeifer, 2006a, Figure 2)

  31. Example: Modus Barbara All philosophers are mortal. All members of the Vienna Circle are philosophers. All members of the Vienna Circle are mortal.

  32. Modus Barbara (A) All M are P (A) All S are M (A) All S are P

  33. Modus Barbara (A) All M are P (A) All S are M (A) All S are P ∀ x ( Mx ⊃ Px ) ( ∧∃ xMx ) (A) ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ Mx ) ( ∧∃ xSx ) (A) ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ Px ) (A)

  34. Modus Barbara (A) All M are P (A) All S are M (A) All S are P ∀ x ( Mx ⊃ Px ) ( ∧∃ xMx ) (A) ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ Mx ) ( ∧∃ xSx ) (A) ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ Px ) (A) Figure name 1 2 3 4 Premise 1 MP PM MP PM Premise 2 SM SM MS MS Conclusion SP SP SP SP . . . transitive structure of Figure 1

  35. Example: Modus Barbari All M are P All S are M At least one S is P ∀ x ( Mx ⊃ Px ) ∃ xMx ∧ ∀ x ( Sx ⊃ Mx ) ∃ xSx ∧ ∃ x ( Sx ∧ Px )

  36. The probability heuristics model (Chater & Oaksford, 1999; Oaksford & Chater, 2009) Definitions of the basic sentences: Quantified statement Prob. interpretation p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 (A) All S are P p ( P ∣ S ) = 0 (E) No S is P p ( P ∣ S ) > 0 (I) Some S are P p ( P ∣ S ) < 1 (O) Some S are not- P

  37. The probability heuristics model (Chater & Oaksford, 1999; Oaksford & Chater, 2009) Definitions of the basic sentences: Quantified statement Prob. interpretation p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 (A) All S are P p ( P ∣ S ) = 0 (E) No S is P p ( P ∣ S ) > 0 (I) Some S are P p ( P ∣ S ) < 1 (O) Some S are not- P 1 − ∆ < p ( P ∣ S ) < 1 Most S are P 0 < p ( P ∣ S ) < ∆ Few S are P . . . where ∆ is small

  38. The probability heuristics model: Probabilistic syllogisms ▸ Assumption: Conditional independence between the end terms (i.e., S and P ) given the middle term (i.e., M ): p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = p ( S ∣ M ) p ( P ∣ M )

  39. The probability heuristics model: Probabilistic syllogisms ▸ Assumption: Conditional independence between the end terms (i.e., S and P ) given the middle term (i.e., M ): p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = p ( S ∣ M ) p ( P ∣ M ) ▸ Sample reconstruction of Modus Barbara (assumed implicitly p ( S ) > 0, p ( M ) > 0): p ( P ∣ M ) = 1 (A) p ( M ∣ S ) = 1 (A) p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = p ( S ∣ M ) p ( P ∣ M ) (CI assumption) p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 (A)

  40. The probability heuristics model: Probabilistic syllogisms ▸ Assumption: Conditional independence between the end terms (i.e., S and P ) given the middle term (i.e., M ): p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = p ( S ∣ M ) p ( P ∣ M ) ▸ Sample reconstruction of Modus Barbara (assumed implicitly p ( S ) > 0, p ( M ) > 0): p ( P ∣ M ) = 1 (A) p ( M ∣ S ) = 1 (A) p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = p ( S ∣ M ) p ( P ∣ M ) (CI assumption) p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 (A) Note, that we do not assume p ( S ) > 0 and p ( M ) > 0 in the coherence framework. Moreover, if p ( S ∣ M ) = 0, then p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = 0.

  41. The probability heuristics model: Probabilistic syllogisms ▸ Assumption: Conditional independence between the end terms (i.e., S and P ) given the middle term (i.e., M ): p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = p ( S ∣ M ) p ( P ∣ M ) ▸ Sample reconstruction of Modus Barbara (assumed implicitly p ( S ) > 0, p ( M ) > 0): p ( P ∣ M ) = 1 (A) p ( M ∣ S ) = 1 (A) p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = p ( S ∣ M ) p ( P ∣ M ) (CI assumption) p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 (A) Note, that we do not assume p ( S ) > 0 and p ( M ) > 0 in the coherence framework. Moreover, if p ( S ∣ M ) = 0, then p ( S ∧ P ∣ M ) = 0. Then, the premises are satisfied but 0 ≤ p ( P ∣ S ) ≤ 1 is coherent. Thus, Modus Barbara does not hold.

  42. Table of contents Introduction Interaction of formal/normative and empirical work Mental probability logic Conditionals under coherence Modus ponens and Modus tollens Paradoxes Probabilistic syllogisms (joint work with Gilio & Sanfilippo) A note on Chater & Oaksford’s probabilistic syllogisms The coherence perspective on syllogisms Concluding remarks References Appendix

  43. Towards a probabilistic semantics CondEv-Formalization: p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 All S are P : and EI p ( P ∣ S ) ≫ . 5 Almost-all S are P : and EI p ( P ∣ S ) > . 5 Most S are P : and EI p ( P ∣ S ) > 0 At least one S is P :

  44. Existential import: Different options ▸ Positive probability of the conditioning event, e.g.: All S are P : p ( S ) > 0 ▸ p ( S ∣ M ) > 0 (and p ( M ∣ P ) > 0) (Dubois, Godo, L´ opez de M` antaras, & Prade, 1993)

  45. Existential import: Different options ▸ Positive probability of the conditioning event, e.g.: All S are P : p ( S ) > 0 ▸ p ( S ∣ M ) > 0 (and p ( M ∣ P ) > 0) (Dubois, Godo, L´ opez de M` antaras, & Prade, 1993) ▸ Replacing the first premise by a logical constraint, e.g.: ⊧ ( M ⊃ P ) p ( M ∣ S ) = 1 p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 ▸ Strengthening the antecedent of the first premise, e.g.: p ( P ∣ S ∧ M ) = 1 p ( M ∣ S ) = 1 p ( P ∣ S ) = 1

  46. Existential import: Different options ▸ Positive probability of the conditioning event, e.g.: All S are P : p ( S ) > 0 ▸ p ( S ∣ M ) > 0 (and p ( M ∣ P ) > 0) (Dubois, Godo, L´ opez de M` antaras, & Prade, 1993) ▸ Replacing the first premise by a logical constraint, e.g.: ⊧ ( M ⊃ P ) p ( M ∣ S ) = 1 p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 ▸ Strengthening the antecedent of the first premise, e.g.: p ( P ∣ S ∧ M ) = 1 p ( M ∣ S ) = 1 p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 ▸ Conditional event EI: Positive probability of the conditioning event, given the disjunction of all conditioning events (Gilio, Pfeifer, & Sanfilippo, in press) : p ( P ∣ M ) = 1 p ( M ∣ S ) = 1 p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) > 0 p ( P ∣ S ) = 1 ▸ p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) > 0 neither implies p ( S ) > 0 nor p ( S ∣ M ) > 0

  47. Probabilistic Figure 1, conditional event EI Premises E.I. Conclusion p ( P ∣ M ) p ( M ∣ S ) p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) p ( P ∣ S ) [ z ′ , z ′′ ] x y t x y 0 [0, 1]

  48. Probabilistic Figure 1, conditional event EI Premises E.I. Conclusion p ( P ∣ M ) p ( M ∣ S ) p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) p ( P ∣ S ) [ z ′ , z ′′ ] x y t x y 0 [0, 1] 1 1 t > 0 [1, 1] (Modus Barbara)

  49. Probabilistic Figure 1, conditional event EI Premises E.I. Conclusion p ( P ∣ M ) p ( M ∣ S ) p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) p ( P ∣ S ) [ z ′ , z ′′ ] x y t x y 0 [0, 1] 1 1 t > 0 [1, 1] (Modus Barbara) [ y , 1 ] 1 y t > 0

  50. Probabilistic Figure 1, conditional event EI Premises E.I. Conclusion p ( P ∣ M ) p ( M ∣ S ) p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) p ( P ∣ S ) [ z ′ , z ′′ ] x y t x y 0 [0, 1] 1 1 t > 0 [1, 1] (Modus Barbara) [ y , 1 ] 1 y t > 0 [ . 9 , . 9 ] .9 1 1 [ . 8 , 1 ] .9 1 .5 [ . 5 , 1 ] .9 1 .2 [ 0 , 1 ] .9 1 .1

  51. Probabilistic Figure 1, conditional event EI Premises E.I. Conclusion p ( P ∣ M ) p ( M ∣ S ) p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) p ( P ∣ S ) [ z ′ , z ′′ ] x y t x y 0 [0, 1] 1 1 t > 0 [1, 1] (Modus Barbara) [ y , 1 ] 1 y t > 0 [ . 9 , . 9 ] .9 1 1 [ . 8 , 1 ] .9 1 .5 [ . 5 , 1 ] .9 1 .2 [ 0 , 1 ] .9 1 .1 ] 0 , 1 ] ] 0 , 1 ] 1 t > 0 (Modus Darii)

  52. Probabilistic Figure 1, conditional event EI Premises E.I. Conclusion p ( P ∣ M ) p ( M ∣ S ) p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) p ( P ∣ S ) [ z ′ , z ′′ ] x y t x y 0 [0, 1] 1 1 t > 0 [1, 1] (Modus Barbara) [ y , 1 ] 1 y t > 0 [ . 9 , . 9 ] .9 1 1 [ . 8 , 1 ] .9 1 .5 [ . 5 , 1 ] .9 1 .2 [ 0 , 1 ] .9 1 .1 ] 0 , 1 ] ] 0 , 1 ] 1 t > 0 (Modus Darii) If p ( S ∣ S ∨ M ) > 0 , then z ′ = max { 0 , xy − ( 1 − t )( 1 − x ) } t z ′′ = min { 1 , ( 1 − x )( 1 − y ) + x t } . (Gilio, Pfeifer, and Sanfilippo (in press). Transitive reasoning with imprecise probabilities . ECSQARU’15.)

  53. Table of contents Introduction Interaction of formal/normative and empirical work Mental probability logic Conditionals under coherence Modus ponens and Modus tollens Paradoxes Probabilistic syllogisms (joint work with Gilio & Sanfilippo) A note on Chater & Oaksford’s probabilistic syllogisms The coherence perspective on syllogisms Concluding remarks References Appendix

  54. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic

  55. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes

  56. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences

  57. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences ▸ . . . and endorse basic nonmonotonic rationality postulates

  58. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences ▸ . . . and endorse basic nonmonotonic rationality postulates ▸ Indicative and counterfactual Conditionals are interpreted as conditional probability assertions

  59. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences ▸ . . . and endorse basic nonmonotonic rationality postulates ▸ Indicative and counterfactual Conditionals are interpreted as conditional probability assertions ▸ True interaction of formal and empirical work: opens interdisciplinary collaborations

  60. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences ▸ . . . and endorse basic nonmonotonic rationality postulates ▸ Indicative and counterfactual Conditionals are interpreted as conditional probability assertions ▸ True interaction of formal and empirical work: opens interdisciplinary collaborations ▸ Quantified statements

  61. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences ▸ . . . and endorse basic nonmonotonic rationality postulates ▸ Indicative and counterfactual Conditionals are interpreted as conditional probability assertions ▸ True interaction of formal and empirical work: opens interdisciplinary collaborations ▸ Quantified statements ▸ Probabilistic notion of existential import ▸ Probabilistic syllogisms

  62. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences ▸ . . . and endorse basic nonmonotonic rationality postulates ▸ Indicative and counterfactual Conditionals are interpreted as conditional probability assertions ▸ True interaction of formal and empirical work: opens interdisciplinary collaborations ▸ Quantified statements ▸ Probabilistic notion of existential import ▸ Probabilistic syllogisms ▸ Managing zero antecedent probabilities is important for ▸ Understanding the Paradox: p ( C ) = 1, therefore 0 ≤ p ( C ∣ A ) ≤ 1 ▸ Existential import assumptions ▸ Counterfactuals

  63. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences ▸ . . . and endorse basic nonmonotonic rationality postulates ▸ Indicative and counterfactual Conditionals are interpreted as conditional probability assertions ▸ True interaction of formal and empirical work: opens interdisciplinary collaborations ▸ Quantified statements ▸ Probabilistic notion of existential import ▸ Probabilistic syllogisms ▸ Managing zero antecedent probabilities is important for ▸ Understanding the Paradox: p ( C ) = 1, therefore 0 ≤ p ( C ∣ A ) ≤ 1 ▸ Existential import assumptions ▸ Counterfactuals ▸ Long term goal: Theory of uncertain inference that is normatively and descriptively adequate

  64. Concluding remarks ▸ Mental probability logic ▸ Coherence based probability logic ▸ Conditionals ▸ Examples: Modus ponens, Modus tollens, Paradoxes ▸ Most people draw coherent inferences ▸ . . . and endorse basic nonmonotonic rationality postulates ▸ Indicative and counterfactual Conditionals are interpreted as conditional probability assertions ▸ True interaction of formal and empirical work: opens interdisciplinary collaborations ▸ Quantified statements ▸ Probabilistic notion of existential import ▸ Probabilistic syllogisms ▸ Managing zero antecedent probabilities is important for ▸ Understanding the Paradox: p ( C ) = 1, therefore 0 ≤ p ( C ∣ A ) ≤ 1 ▸ Existential import assumptions ▸ Counterfactuals ▸ Long term goal: Theory of uncertain inference that is normatively and descriptively adequate Papers available at: www.pfeifer-research.de Contact: <niki.pfeifer@lmu.de>

  65. References I Chater, N., & Oaksford, M. (1999). The probability heuristics model of syllogistic reasoning. Cognitive Psychology , 38 , 191-258. Dubois, D., Godo, L., L´ opez de M` antaras, R., & Prade, H. (1993). Qualitative reasoning with imprecise probabilities. Journal of Intelligent Information Systems , 2 , 319–363. Fugard, A. J. B., Pfeifer, N., Mayerhofer, B., & Kleiter, G. D. (2011a). How people interpret conditionals: Shifts towards the conditional event. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition , 37 (3), 635–648. Gilio, A. (2002). Probabilistic reasoning under coherence in System P. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence , 34 , 5-34.

  66. References II Gilio, A., Pfeifer, N., & Sanfilippo, G. (in press). Transitive reasoning with imprecise probabilities. In Proceedings of the 13 th European conference on symbolic and quantitative approaches to reasoning with uncertainty (ECSQARU 2015). Dordrecht: Springer LNCS. Hailperin, T. (1996). Sentential probability logic. Origins, development, current status, and technical applications . Bethlehem: Lehigh University Press. Oaksford, M., & Chater, N. (2009). Pr´ ecis of “Bayesian rationality: The probabilistic approach to human reasoning”. Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 32 , 69-120. Pfeifer, N. (2006a). Contemporary syllogistics: Comparative and quantitative syllogisms. In G. Kreuzbauer & G. J. W. Dorn (Eds.), Argumentation in Theorie und Praxis: Philosophie und Didaktik des Argumentierens (p. 57-71). Wien: Lit Verlag.

  67. References III Pfeifer, N. (2006b). On mental probability logic . Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Department of Psychology, University of Salzburg. (The abstract is published in The Knowledge Engineering Review , 2008, 23, pp. 217-226; http://www.pfeifer-research.de/pdf/diss.pdf ) Pfeifer, N. (2007). Rational argumentation under uncertainty. In G. Kreuzbauer, N. Gratzl, & E. Hiebl (Eds.), Persuasion und Wissenschaft: Aktuelle Fragestellungen von Rhetorik und Argumentationstheorie (p. 181-191). Wien: Lit Verlag. Pfeifer, N. (2008). A probability logical interpretation of fallacies. In G. Kreuzbauer, N. Gratzl, & E. Hiebl (Eds.), Rhetorische Wissenschaft: Rede und Argumentation in Theorie und Praxis (pp. 225–244). Wien: Lit Verlag. Pfeifer, N. (2010, February). Human conditional reasoning and Aristotle’s Thesis. Talk. PROBNET’10 (Probabilistic networks) workshop, Salzburg (Austria).

  68. References IV Pfeifer, N. (2011). Systematic rationality norms provide research roadmaps and clarity. Commentary on Elqayam & Evans: Subtracting “ought” from “is”: Descriptivism versus normativism in the study of human thinking. Behavioral and Brain Sciences , 34 , 263–264. Pfeifer, N. (2012a). Experiments on Aristotle’s Thesis: Towards an experimental philosophy of conditionals. The Monist , 95 (2), 223–240. Pfeifer, N. (2012b). Naturalized formal epistemology of uncertain reasoning . Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Tilburg University. Pfeifer, N. (2013a). The new psychology of reasoning: A mental probability logical perspective. Thinking & Reasoning , 19 (3–4), 329–345. Pfeifer, N. (2013b). On argument strength. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation. The practical side of probability (pp. 185–193). Dordrecht: Synthese Library (Springer).

  69. References V Pfeifer, N. (2014). Reasoning about uncertain conditionals. Studia Logica , 102 (4), 849-866. (DOI: 10.1007/s11225-013-9505-4) Pfeifer, N., & Douven, I. (2014). Formal epistemology and the new paradigm psychology of reasoning. The Review of Philosophy and Psychology , 5 (2), 199–221. Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2005a). Coherence and nonmonotonicity in human reasoning. Synthese , 146 (1-2), 93-109. Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2005b). Towards a mental probability logic. Psychologica Belgica , 45 (1), 71-99. Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2006). Inference in conditional probability logic. Kybernetika , 42 , 391-404.

  70. References VI Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2007). Human reasoning with imprecise probabilities: Modus ponens and Denying the antecedent. In G. De Cooman, J. Vejnarov´ a, & M. Zaffalon (Eds.), Proceedings of the 5 th international symposium on imprecise probability: Theories and applications (p. 347-356). Prague: SIPTA. Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2009). Framing human inference by coherence based probability logic. Journal of Applied Logic , 7 (2), 206–217. Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2010). The conditional in mental probability logic. In M. Oaksford & N. Chater (Eds.), Cognition and conditionals: Probability and logic in human thought (pp. 153–173). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pfeifer, N., & Kleiter, G. D. (2011). Uncertain deductive reasoning. In K. Manktelow, D. E. Over, & S. Elqayam (Eds.), The science of reason: A Festschrift for Jonathan St. B.T. Evans (p. 145-166). Hove: Psychology Press.

  71. Mental probability logic II ▸ uncertain argument forms ▸ conditional syllogisms (Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2007, 2009) ▸ monotonic and non-monotonic arguments (Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2005a, 2010)

  72. Mental probability logic II ▸ uncertain argument forms ▸ conditional syllogisms (Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2007, 2009) ▸ monotonic and non-monotonic arguments (Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2005a, 2010) ▸ argumentation ▸ strength of argument forms (Pfeifer & Kleiter, 2006) and strength of concrete arguments (Pfeifer, 2007, 2013b) ▸ fallacies (Pfeifer, 2008)

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend