borel determinacy and the word problem for finitely
play

Borel Determinacy and the Word Problem for Finitely Generated Groups - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Borel Determinacy and the Word Problem for Finitely Generated Groups Simon Thomas Rutgers University July 6th 2011 Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011 The word problem for finitely generated groups


  1. Borel Determinacy and the Word Problem for Finitely Generated Groups Simon Thomas Rutgers University July 6th 2011 Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  2. The word problem for finitely generated groups For each n ≥ 1, fix an computable enumeration { w k ( x 1 , · · · , x n ) | k ∈ N } of the words in x 1 , · · · , x n , x − 1 1 , · · · , x − 1 n . Definition If G = � a 1 , · · · , a n � is a finitely generated group, then Word ( G ) = { k ∈ N | w k ( a 1 , · · · , a n ) = 1 } Proposition If G = � a 1 , · · · , a n � = � b 1 , · · · , b m � is a finitely generated group, then { k ∈ N | w k ( a 1 , · · · , a n ) = 1 } ≡ T { ℓ ∈ N | w ℓ ( b 1 , · · · , b m ) = 1 } . Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  3. Prescribing the Turing degree of the word problem Theorem (Folklore) For each subset A ⊆ N , there exists a finitely generated group G A such that Word ( G A ) ≡ T A. Question Does there exist a uniform construction A �→ G A with the property that the isomorphism type of G A only depends upon the Turing degree of A? Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  4. Polish Spaces & Borel maps Definition If ( X , d ) is a complete separable metric space, then the corresponding topological space ( X , T ) is a Polish space. Example The Cantor space 2 N = P ( N ) is a Polish space. Definition If X, Y are Polish spaces, then a function f : X → Y is Borel if graph ( f ) is a Borel subset of X × Y. Church’s Thesis for Real Mathematics EXPLICIT = BOREL Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  5. The Polish space of f.g. groups A marked group ( G , ¯ s ) consists of a f.g. group with a distinguished sequence ¯ s = ( s 1 , · · · , s m ) of generators. For each m ≥ 1, let G m be the set of isomorphism types of marked groups ( G , ( s 1 , · · · , s m )) with m distinguished generators. Then there exists a canonical embedding G m ֒ → G m + 1 defined by ( G , ( s 1 , · · · , s m )) �→ ( G , ( s 1 , · · · , s m , 1 G )) . And G fg = � G m is the space of f.g. groups. Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  6. The Polish space of f.g. groups Let ( G , ¯ s ) ∈ G m and let d S be the corresponding word metric. For each ℓ ≥ 1, let B ℓ ( G , ¯ s ) = { g ∈ G | d S ( g , 1 G ) ≤ ℓ } . The basic open neighborhoods of ( G , ¯ s ) in G m are given by s ) ,ℓ = { ( H , ¯ t ) ∈ G m | B ℓ ( H , ¯ t ) ∼ = B ℓ ( G , ¯ U ( G , ¯ s ) } , ℓ ≥ 1 . Example For each n ≥ 1, let C n = � g n � be cyclic of order n . Then: n →∞ ( C n , g n ) = ( Z , 1 ) . lim Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  7. An inevitable non-uniformity result Theorem Suppose that A �→ G A is any Borel map from 2 N to G fg such that Word ( G A ) ≡ T A for all A ∈ 2 N . Then there exists a Turing degree d 0 such that for all d ≥ T d 0 , there exists an infinite subset { A n | n ∈ N } ⊆ d such that the groups { G A n | n ∈ N } are pairwise incomparable with respect to embeddability. Today we will prove a slighly weaker version: Main Theorem There does not exist a Borel map A �→ G A from 2 N to G fg such that for all A, B ∈ 2 N , Word ( G A ) ≡ T A; and if A ≡ T B then G A ∼ = G B . Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  8. Countable Borel equivalence relations Definition An equivalence relation E on a Polish space X is Borel if E is a Borel subset of X × X. A Borel equivalence relation E is countable if every E-class is countable. Some Examples The isomorphism relation ∼ = is a countable Borel equivalence relation on the space G fg of f.g. groups. The Turing equivalence relation ≡ T is a countable Borel equivalence relation on 2 N . Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  9. Borel reductions Definition Let E, F be Borel equivalence relations on the Polish spaces X, Y respectively. E ≤ B F if there exists a Borel map f : X → Y such that x E y ⇐ ⇒ f ( x ) F f ( y ) . In this case, f is called a Borel reduction from E to F. E ∼ B F if both E ≤ B F and F ≤ B E. E < B F if both E ≤ B F and E ≁ B F. Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  10. Universal countable Borel equivalence relations Definition A countable Borel equivalence relation E is universal if F ≤ B E for every countable Borel equivalence relation F. Theorem (Thomas-Velickovic) The isomorphism relation ∼ = on G fg is a universal countable Borel equivalence relation. Remark It is currently not known whether the Turing equivalence relation ≡ T is countable universal. Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  11. Universal countable Borel equivalence relations Corollary There exists a Borel reduction from ≡ T to ∼ = . Main Theorem There does not exist a Borel reduction A �→ G A from ≡ T to ∼ = such that Word ( G A ) ≡ T A for all A ∈ 2 N . “Equivalently”, there does not exist a continuous reduction from ≡ T to ∼ = . Question (Kanovei) Find natural examples of Borel equivalence relations E, F such that E ≤ B F but there is no continuous reduction from E to F. Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  12. Why are such examples hard to find? Theorem (Folklore) If X, Y are Polish spaces and ϕ : X → Y is a Borel map, then there exists a comeager subset C ⊆ X such that ϕ ↾ C is continuous. Theorem (Lusin) Let X, Y be Polish spaces and let µ be any Borel probability measure on X. If ϕ : X → Y is a Borel map, then for every ε > 0 , there exists a compact set K ⊆ X with µ ( K ) > 1 − ε such that ϕ ↾ K is continuous. Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  13. Another notion of largeness ... Definition For each z ∈ 2 N , the corresponding cone is C z = { x ∈ 2 N | z ≤ T x } . Suppose z n = { a n ,ℓ | ℓ ∈ N } ∈ 2 N for each n ∈ N and define ⊕ z n = { p a n ,ℓ | n , ℓ ∈ N } ∈ 2 N , n where p n is the n th prime. Then z m ≤ T ⊕ z n for each m ∈ N and so C ⊕ z n ⊆ � n C z n . Remark It is well-known that if C � 2 N is a proper cone, then C is both null and meager. Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  14. Continuous maps on the Cantor space Theorem (Folklore) If θ : 2 N → 2 N , then the following are equivalent: (a) θ is continuous. (b) There exists C ∈ 2 N and e ∈ N such that θ ( A ) = ϕ C ⊕ A . e Corollary If θ : 2 N → 2 N is continuous, then there exists a cone C such that θ ( A ) ≤ T A for all A ∈ C . Corollary If G �→ K G is a continuous map from G fg to G fg , then there exists a cone C such that if Word ( G ) ∈ C , then Word ( K G ) ≤ T Word ( G ) . Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  15. The “obvious” vs “nonobvious” Turing reductions ... Definition If A, B ∈ 2 N , then A is one-one reducible to B, written A ≤ 1 B, if there exists an injective recursive function f : N → N such that for all n ∈ N , n ∈ A ⇐ ⇒ f ( n ) ∈ B . Example If G , H ∈ G fg and G ֒ → H , then Word ( G ) ≤ 1 Word ( H ) . Proof. Suppose that G = � a 1 , · · · , a n � and H = � b 1 , · · · , b m � . Let ϕ : G → H be an embedding and let ϕ ( a i ) = t i (¯ b ) . Then w k ( t 1 (¯ b ) , · · · , t n (¯ w k ( a 1 , · · · , a n ) = 1 ⇐ ⇒ b )) = 1 . Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  16. Turing Equivalence vs. Recursive Isomorphism Definition The sets A, B ∈ 2 N are recursively isomorphic, written A ≡ 1 B, if both A ≤ 1 B and B ≤ 1 A. Theorem (Myhill) If A, B ∈ 2 N , then A ≡ 1 B if and only if there exists a recursive permutation π ∈ Sym ( N ) such that π [ A ] = B. Theorem (Folklore) The map A �→ A ′ is a Borel reduction from ≡ T to ≡ 1 . Observation The Borel reduction A �→ A ′ from ≡ T to ≡ 1 is certainly not continuous. Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  17. Turing Equivalence vs. Recursive Isomorphism Definition Let E, F be Borel equivalence relations on the Polish spaces X, Y. Then the Borel map ϕ : X → Y is a homomorphism from E to F if x E y = ⇒ ϕ ( x ) F ϕ ( y ) . Main Lemma If θ : 2 N → 2 N is a continuous homomorphism from ≡ T to ≡ 1 , then there exists a cone C such that θ maps C into a single ≡ 1 -class. Corollary There does not exist a continuous reduction from ≡ T to ≡ 1 . Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

  18. Turing Equivalence vs. Isomorphism on G fg Corollary There does not exist a continuous reduction from ≡ T to ∼ = . Proof. Suppose A �→ H A is a continuous reduction from ≡ T to ∼ = . Note that H �→ Word ( H ) is an injective continuous homomorphism from ∼ = to ≡ 1 . Thus A �→ Word ( H A ) is a countable-to-one continuous homomorphism from ≡ T to ≡ 1 , which is a contradiction. Simon Thomas (Rutgers University) 8th Panhellenic Logic Symposium July 6th 2011

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend