an inferentialist account of implicit definition
play

An Inferentialist Account of (Implicit) Definition Dan Kaplan - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion An Inferentialist Account of (Implicit) Definition Dan Kaplan University of Pittsburgh / Universitt Leipzig dan.kaplan@pitt.edu PhDs in Logic X May 2 nd , 2018 pitt.edu/


  1. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Implicit Definitions Analogy with “reference fixing”: “Jack the Ripper is the man responsible for these murders.” (i.e. those that occurred in Whitechapel in the latter half of 1888) Some (potential) problems: Existence: How do we know that anyone is referred to by Jack the Ripper? Uniqueness: How do we know there is a unique such person?

  2. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Implicit Definitions Analogy with “reference fixing”: “Jack the Ripper is the man responsible for these murders.” (i.e. those that occurred in Whitechapel in the latter half of 1888) Some (potential) problems: Existence: How do we know that anyone is referred to by Jack the Ripper? Uniqueness: How do we know there is a unique such person? Possession: What does it mean that the term comes to possess this meaning.

  3. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Implicit Definitions Analogy with “reference fixing”: “Jack the Ripper is the man responsible for these murders.” (i.e. those that occurred in Whitechapel in the latter half of 1888) Some (potential) problems: Existence: How do we know that anyone is referred to by Jack the Ripper? Uniqueness: How do we know there is a unique such person? Possession: What does it mean that the term comes to possess this meaning. Explanation: We must explain this process: how is it that asserting a sentence confers possession of a meaning to a term.

  4. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Implicit Definitions Analogy with “reference fixing”: “Jack the Ripper is the man responsible for these murders.” (i.e. those that occurred in Whitechapel in the latter half of 1888) Some (potential) problems: Existence: How do we know that anyone is referred to by Jack the Ripper? Uniqueness: How do we know there is a unique such person? Possession: What does it mean that the term comes to possess this meaning. Explanation: We must explain this process: how is it that asserting a sentence confers possession of a meaning to a term. Suggestion: Ramsify + Carnap Conditional. Schema ‘ # _’: ∃ x (# x ) → # f .

  5. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem Layout Definitions 1 Explicit Definitions Implicit Definitions Beth’s Theorem Inferentialism 2 Definitions (revisited) 3 Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Conclusion 4

  6. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem Theorem (Beth’s Theorem) ‘ f ’ is implicitly definable iff ‘ f ’ is explicitly definable (i.e. exists an explicit definition for ‘ f ’ equivalent to its implicit definition).

  7. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem Theorem (Beth’s Theorem) ‘ f ’ is implicitly definable iff ‘ f ’ is explicitly definable (i.e. exists an explicit definition for ‘ f ’ equivalent to its implicit definition). Proof. ( ⇒ )[Padoa’s Method] Let α ↔ B explicitly define ‘ f ’. ‘ α ↔ B ’ may serve as ‘ f ’s implicit definition. �

  8. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Continued) Proof. ( ⇐ )[over-simplification from Craig’s Interpolation Lemma]

  9. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Continued) Proof. ( ⇐ )[over-simplification from Craig’s Interpolation Lemma] Suppose Craig’s Lemma holds in our logic and that α implicitly defines ‘ f ’. If we introduce a second f ′ implicitly defined by α ′ then they are equivalent:

  10. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Continued) Proof. ( ⇐ )[over-simplification from Craig’s Interpolation Lemma] Suppose Craig’s Lemma holds in our logic and that α implicitly defines ‘ f ’. If we introduce a second f ′ implicitly defined by α ′ then they are equivalent: α ↔ α ′ .

  11. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Continued) Proof. ( ⇐ )[over-simplification from Craig’s Interpolation Lemma] Suppose Craig’s Lemma holds in our logic and that α implicitly defines ‘ f ’. If we introduce a second f ′ implicitly defined by α ′ then they are equivalent: α ↔ α ′ . By Craig’s Lemma exists B (with proper characteristics) such that: α ⇔ B ⇔ α ′

  12. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Continued) Proof. ( ⇐ )[over-simplification from Craig’s Interpolation Lemma] Suppose Craig’s Lemma holds in our logic and that α implicitly defines ‘ f ’. If we introduce a second f ′ implicitly defined by α ′ then they are equivalent: α ↔ α ′ . By Craig’s Lemma exists B (with proper characteristics) such that: α ⇔ B ⇔ α ′ Explicit definition is: α ⇔ B . �

  13. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem Theorem ‘ f ’ is implicitly definable iff ‘ f ’ is explicitly definable (i.e. exists an explicit definition for ‘ f ’ equivalent to its implicit definition). NB1: ( ⇒ ) is not trivial. NB2: As evidenced by Craig’s Lemma, we must presuppose something like classical logic to get Beth’s Theorem.

  14. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Layout Definitions 1 Explicit Definitions Implicit Definitions Beth’s Theorem Inferentialism 2 Definitions (revisited) 3 Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Conclusion 4

  15. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Recall: Goal: Account of genuine implicit definition.

  16. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Recall: Goal: Account of genuine implicit definition. Suggestion: Move to sub-/non-classical logic. Use different theory of meaning (i.e. not truth functional).

  17. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Suppose following lists are exhaustive: p , Γ 1 ⊢ Θ 1 ∆ 1 ⊢ Λ 1 , p . . . . . . p , Γ n ⊢ Θ n ∆ m ⊢ Λ m , p . . . . . . Suggestion: let us understand the meaning of ‘ p ’ in terms of its behavior in reasoning.

  18. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Some useful shorthands/definitions:

  19. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Some useful shorthands/definitions: I : Let I be the set of good implications. I.e. those sets of sentences related by ‘ ⊢ ’. Clearly I ⊆ P ( L ) 2 (where L is the set of all sentences).

  20. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Some useful shorthands/definitions: I : Let I be the set of good implications. I.e. those sets of sentences related by ‘ ⊢ ’. Clearly I ⊆ P ( L ) 2 (where L is the set of all sentences). ⊔ : Let ‘ ⊔ ’ ( fuission ) be a pairwise set-union operation for ordered pairs. Thus � Γ , Θ � ⊔ � ∆ , Λ � = df . � Γ ∪ ∆ , Θ ∪ Λ � .

  21. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Some useful shorthands/definitions: I : Let I be the set of good implications. I.e. those sets of sentences related by ‘ ⊢ ’. Clearly I ⊆ P ( L ) 2 (where L is the set of all sentences). ⊔ : Let ‘ ⊔ ’ ( fuission ) be a pairwise set-union operation for ordered pairs. Thus � Γ , Θ � ⊔ � ∆ , Λ � = df . � Γ ∪ ∆ , Θ ∪ Λ � . Occasionally I might use ‘ ⊔ ’ as on operation on sets of ordered pairs of sets of sentences, i.e. suppose X , Y ⊆ P ( L ) . Then we should understand X ⊔ Y as: X ⊔ Y = df . { x ⊔ y | x ∈ X , y ∈ Y } , i.e., the result of applying ‘ ⊔ ’ to x and y for each x ∈ X and y ∈ Y .

  22. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion � : Let us understand ‘ � ’ (pronounced: “vee”) as a function that maps (in the basic case) an ordered pair to a set of ordered pairs whose fuission makes a good inference. So, for example: � Γ , Θ � � = df . {� ∆ , Λ �|� Γ , Θ � ⊔ � ∆ , Λ � ∈ I } .

  23. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion � : Let us understand ‘ � ’ (pronounced: “vee”) as a function that maps (in the basic case) an ordered pair to a set of ordered pairs whose fuission makes a good inference. So, for example: � Γ , Θ � � = df . {� ∆ , Λ �|� Γ , Θ � ⊔ � ∆ , Λ � ∈ I } . Similarly we may define the same over sets of ordered pairs, where the result amounts to the intersection of the same of each of its members: X � = df . {� ∆ , Λ �|∀� Γ , Θ � ∈ X ( � Γ , Θ � ⊔ � ∆ , Λ � ∈ I ) } .

  24. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion � : Let us understand ‘ � ’ (pronounced: “vee”) as a function that maps (in the basic case) an ordered pair to a set of ordered pairs whose fuission makes a good inference. So, for example: � Γ , Θ � � = df . {� ∆ , Λ �|� Γ , Θ � ⊔ � ∆ , Λ � ∈ I } . Similarly we may define the same over sets of ordered pairs, where the result amounts to the intersection of the same of each of its members: X � = df . {� ∆ , Λ �|∀� Γ , Θ � ∈ X ( � Γ , Θ � ⊔ � ∆ , Λ � ∈ I ) } . ‘ ⊔ ’ and ‘ � ’ together give us a neat way to talk about the role that a sentence, e.g. p , plays in good implication. We can think of interpreting p thusly: � p � = df . ��{ p } , ∅� � , �∅ , { p }� � � .

  25. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Proper Inferential Role (PIR): Let X = � Y , Z � specify an inferential role (i.e. the contribution that a sentence might make to good implication). We call X a proper inferential role if X �� = X .

  26. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Proper Inferential Role (PIR): Let X = � Y , Z � specify an inferential role (i.e. the contribution that a sentence might make to good implication). We call X a proper inferential role if X �� = X . Shorthand, if: � A � = df . � X , Y � . Then: � A � P = df . = X � A � C = df . = Y .

  27. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Proper Inferential Role (PIR): Let X = � Y , Z � specify an inferential role (i.e. the contribution that a sentence might make to good implication). We call X a proper inferential role if X �� = X . Shorthand, if: � A � = df . � X , Y � . Then: � A � P = df . = X � A � C = df . = Y . Conditional ( → ): � A → B � = df . � � A � C ∩ � B � P , (( � A � P ) � ⊔ ( � B � C ) � ) � � . Negation ( ¬ ): � ¬ A � = df . � � A � C , � A � P � .

  28. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Proper Inferential Role (PIR): Let X = � Y , Z � specify an inferential role (i.e. the contribution that a sentence might make to good implication). We call X a proper inferential role if X �� = X . Shorthand, if: � A � = df . � X , Y � . Then: � A � P = df . = X � A � C = df . = Y . Conditional ( → ): � A → B � = df . � � A � C ∩ � B � P , (( � A � P ) � ⊔ ( � B � C ) � ) � � . Negation ( ¬ ): � ¬ A � = df . � � A � C , � A � P � . Conjunction ( & ) and Disjunction ( ∨ ) defined analogously.

  29. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Base Consequence Relation) ∼ 0 ⊆ P ( L 0 ) 2 . Let |

  30. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Base Consequence Relation) ∼ 0 ⊆ P ( L 0 ) 2 . Let | Axiom: If Γ 0 | ∼ 0 Θ 0 , then Γ 0 | ∼ Θ 0 .

  31. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Base Consequence Relation) ∼ 0 ⊆ P ( L 0 ) 2 . Let | Axiom: If Γ 0 | ∼ 0 Θ 0 , then Γ 0 | ∼ Θ 0 . Γ ⊢ Θ , A B , Γ ⊢ Θ A , Γ ⊢ Θ , B L → R → A → B , Γ ⊢ Θ Γ ⊢ A → B , Θ Γ ⊢ Θ , A A , Γ ⊢ Θ L ¬ R ¬ ¬ A , Γ ⊢ Θ Γ ⊢ Θ , ¬ A

  32. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Base Consequence Relation) ∼ 0 ⊆ P ( L 0 ) 2 . Let | Axiom: If Γ 0 | ∼ 0 Θ 0 , then Γ 0 | ∼ Θ 0 . Γ ⊢ Θ , A B , Γ ⊢ Θ A , Γ ⊢ Θ , B L → R → A → B , Γ ⊢ Θ Γ ⊢ A → B , Θ Γ ⊢ Θ , A A , Γ ⊢ Θ L ¬ R ¬ ¬ A , Γ ⊢ Θ Γ ⊢ Θ , ¬ A Conjunction ( & ) and Disjunction ( ∨ ) defined analogously.

  33. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Semantic Entailment) We say that A semantically entails B relative to a model M if closure of the fuission of A (as premise) and B (as conclusion) consists of only good implications: (( � A � P ) � ⊔ ( � B � C ) � ) �� ⊆ I M . iff df . A � M B

  34. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Semantic Entailment) We say that A semantically entails B relative to a model M if closure of the fuission of A (as premise) and B (as conclusion) consists of only good implications: (( � A � P ) � ⊔ ( � B � C ) � ) �� ⊆ I M . iff df . A � M B We say that A semantically entails B if A � M B on all models M .

  35. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Semantic Entailment) We say that A semantically entails B relative to a model M if closure of the fuission of A (as premise) and B (as conclusion) consists of only good implications: (( � A � P ) � ⊔ ( � B � C ) � ) �� ⊆ I M . iff df . A � M B We say that A semantically entails B if A � M B on all models M . NB: If A and B are sets of sentences then we read A ⊢ B as & A ⊢ ∨ B , i.e. the conjunction of the elements of A and the disjunction of the elements of B .

  36. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Base Consequence Relation) A base consequence relation is a subset of P that consists of only atoms. B is a base consequence relation iff B ⊆ P and B ∩ P ( L 0 ) 2 = B .

  37. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Base Consequence Relation) A base consequence relation is a subset of P that consists of only atoms. B is a base consequence relation iff B ⊆ P and B ∩ P ( L 0 ) 2 = B . We say that a model M = � P , I , � · � � is fit for a base consequence relation B iff ∀� ∆ , Λ � ∈ B (∆ � M Λ) .

  38. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Definition (Base Consequence Relation) A base consequence relation is a subset of P that consists of only atoms. B is a base consequence relation iff B ⊆ P and B ∩ P ( L 0 ) 2 = B . We say that a model M = � P , I , � · � � is fit for a base consequence relation B iff ∀� ∆ , Λ � ∈ B (∆ � M Λ) . We say that Γ semantically entails Θ relative to B iff Γ � M Θ for all models M fit for B .

  39. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Soundness and Completeness Theorem (Soundness) The sequent calculus is sound: Γ ⊢ B Θ ⇒ Γ � B Θ . Theorem (Completeness) The sequent calculus is complete: Γ � B Θ ⇒ Γ ⊢ B Θ .

  40. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Layout Definitions 1 Explicit Definitions Implicit Definitions Beth’s Theorem Inferentialism 2 Definitions (revisited) 3 Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Conclusion 4

  41. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion I explore five notions of “definability” (ways in which a new term may be successfully given a meaning).

  42. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion I explore five notions of “definability” (ways in which a new term may be successfully given a meaning). ∆ 1 Explicit Definition: A ↔ B . Introduced as: A ⊢ B and B ⊢ A .

  43. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion I explore five notions of “definability” (ways in which a new term may be successfully given a meaning). ∆ 1 Explicit Definition: A ↔ B . Introduced as: A ⊢ B and B ⊢ A . ∆ 2 Explicit (Inferential) Definition: A = df . B licenses: B , Γ ⊢ Θ ⇒ A , Γ ⊢ Θ and Γ ⊢ Θ , B ⇒ Γ ⊢ Θ , A .

  44. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion I explore five notions of “definability” (ways in which a new term may be successfully given a meaning). ∆ 1 Explicit Definition: A ↔ B . Introduced as: A ⊢ B and B ⊢ A . ∆ 2 Explicit (Inferential) Definition: A = df . B licenses: B , Γ ⊢ Θ ⇒ A , Γ ⊢ Θ and Γ ⊢ Θ , B ⇒ Γ ⊢ Θ , A . ∆ 3 Inferential Definition: A = df . � B , C � licenses: B , Γ ⊢ Θ ⇒ A , Γ ⊢ Θ and Γ ⊢ Θ , C ⇒ Γ ⊢ Θ , A .

  45. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion I explore five notions of “definability” (ways in which a new term may be successfully given a meaning). ∆ 1 Explicit Definition: A ↔ B . Introduced as: A ⊢ B and B ⊢ A . ∆ 2 Explicit (Inferential) Definition: A = df . B licenses: B , Γ ⊢ Θ ⇒ A , Γ ⊢ Θ and Γ ⊢ Θ , B ⇒ Γ ⊢ Θ , A . ∆ 3 Inferential Definition: A = df . � B , C � licenses: B , Γ ⊢ Θ ⇒ A , Γ ⊢ Θ and Γ ⊢ Θ , C ⇒ Γ ⊢ Θ , A . ∆ 4 Implicit Definition: A term p is defined implicitly if the stipulation that all the implications in I successfully give p a meaning (i.e. it is not possible to construct models which disagree about the meaning of p ).

  46. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion I explore five notions of “definability” (ways in which a new term may be successfully given a meaning). ∆ 1 Explicit Definition: A ↔ B . Introduced as: A ⊢ B and B ⊢ A . ∆ 2 Explicit (Inferential) Definition: A = df . B licenses: B , Γ ⊢ Θ ⇒ A , Γ ⊢ Θ and Γ ⊢ Θ , B ⇒ Γ ⊢ Θ , A . ∆ 3 Inferential Definition: A = df . � B , C � licenses: B , Γ ⊢ Θ ⇒ A , Γ ⊢ Θ and Γ ⊢ Θ , C ⇒ Γ ⊢ Θ , A . ∆ 4 Implicit Definition: A term p is defined implicitly if the stipulation that all the implications in I successfully give p a meaning (i.e. it is not possible to construct models which disagree about the meaning of p ). ∆ 5 Proper Inferential Role: (Compare above)

  47. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Some interesting results:

  48. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Some interesting results: ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 5 .

  49. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Some interesting results: ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 5 . From this follows a modified version of Padoa’s result: ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 5 .

  50. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Some interesting results: ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 5 . From this follows a modified version of Padoa’s result: ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 5 . NB: None of the converses hold without further stipulation.

  51. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Recall sentences interpreted: � A � = df . � X , Y � , where X �� = X and Y �� = Y .

  52. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Recall sentences interpreted: � A � = df . � X , Y � , where X �� = X and Y �� = Y . Definition (Functional Completeness) We call our logic:

  53. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Recall sentences interpreted: � A � = df . � X , Y � , where X �� = X and Y �� = Y . Definition (Functional Completeness) We call our logic: Φ 1 : If for any Z �� ⊆ P ( L ) 2 there exists A ∈ L such that: � A � P = Z �� � A � C = Z �� . OR

  54. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Recall sentences interpreted: � A � = df . � X , Y � , where X �� = X and Y �� = Y . Definition (Functional Completeness) We call our logic: Φ 1 : If for any Z �� ⊆ P ( L ) 2 there exists A ∈ L such that: � A � P = Z �� � A � C = Z �� . OR ⊆ P ( L ) 2 exists A ∈ L such that: Φ 2 : If for any Z �� , Z �� 1 2 � A � = � Z �� , Z �� � . 1 2

  55. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion The converses:

  56. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion The converses: ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 3 : Implicit definitions collapse to inferential definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 1 (see above). Stipulating contraction and weakening are sufficient to force Φ 1 .

  57. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion The converses: ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 3 : Implicit definitions collapse to inferential definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 1 (see above). Stipulating contraction and weakening are sufficient to force Φ 1 . ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Inferential definitions collapse to explicit (inferential) definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 2 . It is sufficient that the logic is restricted such that it obeys reflexivity and Cut-Elimination (meaning we can find Interpolants).

  58. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion The converses: ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 3 : Implicit definitions collapse to inferential definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 1 (see above). Stipulating contraction and weakening are sufficient to force Φ 1 . ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Inferential definitions collapse to explicit (inferential) definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 2 . It is sufficient that the logic is restricted such that it obeys reflexivity and Cut-Elimination (meaning we can find Interpolants). ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 1 : Given transitivity.

  59. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion The converses: ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 3 : Implicit definitions collapse to inferential definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 1 (see above). Stipulating contraction and weakening are sufficient to force Φ 1 . ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Inferential definitions collapse to explicit (inferential) definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 2 . It is sufficient that the logic is restricted such that it obeys reflexivity and Cut-Elimination (meaning we can find Interpolants). ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 1 : Given transitivity. ∆ 1 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Given reflexivity.

  60. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion The converses: ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 3 : Implicit definitions collapse to inferential definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 1 (see above). Stipulating contraction and weakening are sufficient to force Φ 1 . ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Inferential definitions collapse to explicit (inferential) definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 2 . It is sufficient that the logic is restricted such that it obeys reflexivity and Cut-Elimination (meaning we can find Interpolants). ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 1 : Given transitivity. ∆ 1 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Given reflexivity. Note that if the consequence relation is stipulated to be supra-classical then all the above notions of definitions will collapse:

  61. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion The converses: ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 3 : Implicit definitions collapse to inferential definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 1 (see above). Stipulating contraction and weakening are sufficient to force Φ 1 . ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Inferential definitions collapse to explicit (inferential) definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 2 . It is sufficient that the logic is restricted such that it obeys reflexivity and Cut-Elimination (meaning we can find Interpolants). ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 1 : Given transitivity. ∆ 1 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Given reflexivity. Note that if the consequence relation is stipulated to be supra-classical then all the above notions of definitions will collapse: ∆ 1 ⇔ ∆ 2 ⇔ ∆ 3 ⇔ ∆ 4 .

  62. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion The converses: ∆ 4 ⇒ ∆ 3 : Implicit definitions collapse to inferential definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 1 (see above). Stipulating contraction and weakening are sufficient to force Φ 1 . ∆ 3 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Inferential definitions collapse to explicit (inferential) definitions if the underlying logic is Φ 2 . It is sufficient that the logic is restricted such that it obeys reflexivity and Cut-Elimination (meaning we can find Interpolants). ∆ 2 ⇒ ∆ 1 : Given transitivity. ∆ 1 ⇒ ∆ 2 : Given reflexivity. Note that if the consequence relation is stipulated to be supra-classical then all the above notions of definitions will collapse: ∆ 1 ⇔ ∆ 2 ⇔ ∆ 3 ⇔ ∆ 4 . NB: This version is independent of Craig’s Lemma.

  63. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Layout Definitions 1 Explicit Definitions Implicit Definitions Beth’s Theorem Inferentialism 2 Definitions (revisited) 3 Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Conclusion 4

  64. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Two analogs to Beth’s Theorem:

  65. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Two analogs to Beth’s Theorem: Theorem (Beth’s Theorem) If ⊢ is supra-classical then a definition is ∆ 1 iff it is ∆ 4 . I.e. the class of explicit definitions ( ∆ 1 ) and the class of implicit definitions ( ∆ 4 ) are coextensive.

  66. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Two analogs to Beth’s Theorem: Theorem (Beth’s Theorem) If ⊢ is supra-classical then a definition is ∆ 1 iff it is ∆ 4 . I.e. the class of explicit definitions ( ∆ 1 ) and the class of implicit definitions ( ∆ 4 ) are coextensive. I’ll also introduce an analog of interest (insofar as it lets us look at the relationship between notions I have introduced).

  67. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Two analogs to Beth’s Theorem: Theorem (Beth’s Theorem) If ⊢ is supra-classical then a definition is ∆ 1 iff it is ∆ 4 . I.e. the class of explicit definitions ( ∆ 1 ) and the class of implicit definitions ( ∆ 4 ) are coextensive. I’ll also introduce an analog of interest (insofar as it lets us look at the relationship between notions I have introduced). Theorem (Alternative to Beth’s Theorem) If our logic is Φ 2 , then a definition is ∆ 2 iff it is ∆ 4 . That is, the class of explicit (inferential) definitions and those of implicit definitions are coextensive.

  68. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Layout Definitions 1 Explicit Definitions Implicit Definitions Beth’s Theorem Inferentialism 2 Definitions (revisited) 3 Beth’s Theorem (Revisited) Conclusion 4

  69. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Goal: Account of genuine implicit definition.

  70. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Goal: Account of genuine implicit definition. Explored space that opens up when we move to a sub-/non-classical setting and an alternative theory of meaning.

  71. Definitions Inferentialism Definitions (revisited) Conclusion Goal: Account of genuine implicit definition. Explored space that opens up when we move to a sub-/non-classical setting and an alternative theory of meaning. Not explored: Eliminability requires some notion of “equivalence”, how am I understanding this? Why do I call what I am doing “definition”. Some of what counts as definition looks quite strange.

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend