topological semantics of polymodal provability logic
play

Topological semantics of polymodal provability logic Lev - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Topological semantics of polymodal provability logic Lev Beklemishev Steklov Mathematical Institute, Moscow In memoriam Leo Esakia TACL, Marseille, July 2630, 2011 Lindenbaum algebras Lindenbaum algebra of a theory T : L T = { sentences of


  1. Topological semantics of polymodal provability logic Lev Beklemishev Steklov Mathematical Institute, Moscow In memoriam Leo Esakia TACL, Marseille, July 26–30, 2011

  2. Lindenbaum algebras Lindenbaum algebra of a theory T : L T = { sentences of T } / ∼ T , where ϕ ∼ T ψ ⇐ ⇒ T ⊢ ( ϕ ↔ ψ ) L T is a boolean algebra with operations ∧ , ∨ , ¬ . 1 = the set of provable sentences of T 0 = the set of refutable sentences of T For consistent g¨ odelian T all such algebras are countable atomless, hence pairwise isomorphic. Kripke, Pour-El: even computably isomorphic

  3. Magari algebras Emerged in 1970s: Macintyre/Simmons, Magari, Smory´ nski, . . . Let T be a g¨ odelian theory (formalizing its own syntax), Con ( T ) = « T is consistent» Consistency operator ✸ : ϕ �− → Con ( T + ϕ ) acting on L T . ( L T , ✸ ) = Magari algebra of T ✷ ϕ = ¬ ✸ ¬ ϕ = « ϕ is provable in T » Characteristic of ( M , ✸ ) : ch ( M ) = min { k : ✸ k 1 = 0 } ; ch ( M ) = ∞ , if no such k exists. Remark. If N � T , then ch ( L T ) = ∞ .

  4. Magari algebras Emerged in 1970s: Macintyre/Simmons, Magari, Smory´ nski, . . . Let T be a g¨ odelian theory (formalizing its own syntax), Con ( T ) = « T is consistent» Consistency operator ✸ : ϕ �− → Con ( T + ϕ ) acting on L T . ( L T , ✸ ) = Magari algebra of T ✷ ϕ = ¬ ✸ ¬ ϕ = « ϕ is provable in T » Characteristic of ( M , ✸ ) : ch ( M ) = min { k : ✸ k 1 = 0 } ; ch ( M ) = ∞ , if no such k exists. Remark. If N � T , then ch ( L T ) = ∞ .

  5. Identities of Magari algebras K. G¨ odel (33), M.H. L¨ ob (55): Algebra ( L T , ✸ ) satisfies the following set of identities GL : boolean identities ✸ 0 = 0 ✸ ( ϕ ∨ ψ ) = ( ✸ ϕ ∨ ✸ ψ ) ✸ ϕ = ✸ ( ϕ ∧ ¬ ✸ ϕ ) (L¨ ob’s identity) GL -algebras = Magari algebras = diagonalizable algebras

  6. Identities of Magari algebras K. G¨ odel (33), M.H. L¨ ob (55): Algebra ( L T , ✸ ) satisfies the following set of identities GL : boolean identities ✸ 0 = 0 ✸ ( ϕ ∨ ψ ) = ( ✸ ϕ ∨ ✸ ψ ) ✸ ϕ = ✸ ( ϕ ∧ ¬ ✸ ϕ ) (L¨ ob’s identity) GL -algebras = Magari algebras = diagonalizable algebras

  7. Provability logic Let A = ( A , ✸ ) be a boolean algebra with an operator ✸ , and ϕ ( � x ) a term. Def. Denote A � ϕ if A � ∀ � x ( ϕ ( � x ) = 1 ) ; The logic of A is Log ( A ) = { ϕ : A � ϕ } . R. Solovay (76): If ch ( L T ) = ∞ , then Log ( L T , ✸ ) = GL . GL is nice as a modal logic (decidable, Kripke complete, fmp, Craig, cut-free calculus, . . . )

  8. Provability logic Let A = ( A , ✸ ) be a boolean algebra with an operator ✸ , and ϕ ( � x ) a term. Def. Denote A � ϕ if A � ∀ � x ( ϕ ( � x ) = 1 ) ; The logic of A is Log ( A ) = { ϕ : A � ϕ } . R. Solovay (76): If ch ( L T ) = ∞ , then Log ( L T , ✸ ) = GL . GL is nice as a modal logic (decidable, Kripke complete, fmp, Craig, cut-free calculus, . . . )

  9. Provability logic Let A = ( A , ✸ ) be a boolean algebra with an operator ✸ , and ϕ ( � x ) a term. Def. Denote A � ϕ if A � ∀ � x ( ϕ ( � x ) = 1 ) ; The logic of A is Log ( A ) = { ϕ : A � ϕ } . R. Solovay (76): If ch ( L T ) = ∞ , then Log ( L T , ✸ ) = GL . GL is nice as a modal logic (decidable, Kripke complete, fmp, Craig, cut-free calculus, . . . )

  10. n -consistency Def. A g¨ odelian theory T is n -consistent, if every provable Σ 0 n -sentence of T is true. n -Con ( T ) = « T is n -consistent» n -consistency operator � n � : L T → L T ϕ �− → n -Con ( T + ϕ ) . [ n ] = ¬� n �¬ ( n -provability)

  11. The algebra of n -provability M T = ( L T ; � 0 � , � 1 � , . . . ) . The following identities GLP hold in M T : GL , for all � n � ; � n + 1 � ϕ → � n � ϕ ; � n � ϕ → [ n + 1 ] � n � ϕ . G. Japaridze (86): If N � T , then Log ( M T ) = GLP .

  12. The algebra of n -provability M T = ( L T ; � 0 � , � 1 � , . . . ) . The following identities GLP hold in M T : GL , for all � n � ; � n + 1 � ϕ → � n � ϕ ; � n � ϕ → [ n + 1 ] � n � ϕ . G. Japaridze (86): If N � T , then Log ( M T ) = GLP .

  13. The significance of GLP GLP is Useful for proof theory: Ordinal notations and consistency proof for PA; Independent combinatorial assertion; Characterization of provably total computable functions of PA. Fairly complicated and not so nice modal-logically: no Kripke completeness, no cut-free calculus; though it is decidable and has Craig interpolation. GLP n is GLP in the language with n operators. GLP 1 = GL .

  14. The significance of GLP GLP is Useful for proof theory: Ordinal notations and consistency proof for PA; Independent combinatorial assertion; Characterization of provably total computable functions of PA. Fairly complicated and not so nice modal-logically: no Kripke completeness, no cut-free calculus; though it is decidable and has Craig interpolation. GLP n is GLP in the language with n operators. GLP 1 = GL .

  15. The significance of GLP GLP is Useful for proof theory: Ordinal notations and consistency proof for PA; Independent combinatorial assertion; Characterization of provably total computable functions of PA. Fairly complicated and not so nice modal-logically: no Kripke completeness, no cut-free calculus; though it is decidable and has Craig interpolation. GLP n is GLP in the language with n operators. GLP 1 = GL .

  16. Set-theoretic interpretation Let X be a nonempty set, P ( X ) the b.a. of subsets of X . Consider any operator δ : P ( X ) → P ( X ) and the structure ( P ( X ) , δ ) . Question: Can ( P ( X ) , δ ) be a GL -algebra and, if yes, when? Def. Write ( X , δ ) � ϕ if ( P ( X ) , δ ) � ϕ . Also let Log ( X , δ ) := Log ( P ( X ) , δ ) .

  17. Set-theoretic interpretation Let X be a nonempty set, P ( X ) the b.a. of subsets of X . Consider any operator δ : P ( X ) → P ( X ) and the structure ( P ( X ) , δ ) . Question: Can ( P ( X ) , δ ) be a GL -algebra and, if yes, when? Def. Write ( X , δ ) � ϕ if ( P ( X ) , δ ) � ϕ . Also let Log ( X , δ ) := Log ( P ( X ) , δ ) .

  18. Set-theoretic interpretation Let X be a nonempty set, P ( X ) the b.a. of subsets of X . Consider any operator δ : P ( X ) → P ( X ) and the structure ( P ( X ) , δ ) . Question: Can ( P ( X ) , δ ) be a GL -algebra and, if yes, when? Def. Write ( X , δ ) � ϕ if ( P ( X ) , δ ) � ϕ . Also let Log ( X , δ ) := Log ( P ( X ) , δ ) .

  19. Derived set operators Let X be a topological space, A ⊆ X . Derived set d ( A ) of A is the set of limit points of A : x ∈ d ( A ) ⇐ ⇒ ∀ U x open ∃ y � = x y ∈ U x ∩ A . Fact. If ( X , δ ) � GL then X naturally bears a topology τ for which δ = d τ , that is, δ : A �− → d τ ( A ) , for each A ⊆ X . In fact, we can define: A is τ -closed iff δ ( A ) ⊆ A . Equivalently, c ( A ) = A ∪ δ ( A ) is the closure of A .

  20. Derived set operators Let X be a topological space, A ⊆ X . Derived set d ( A ) of A is the set of limit points of A : x ∈ d ( A ) ⇐ ⇒ ∀ U x open ∃ y � = x y ∈ U x ∩ A . Fact. If ( X , δ ) � GL then X naturally bears a topology τ for which δ = d τ , that is, δ : A �− → d τ ( A ) , for each A ⊆ X . In fact, we can define: A is τ -closed iff δ ( A ) ⊆ A . Equivalently, c ( A ) = A ∪ δ ( A ) is the closure of A .

  21. Derived set operators Let X be a topological space, A ⊆ X . Derived set d ( A ) of A is the set of limit points of A : x ∈ d ( A ) ⇐ ⇒ ∀ U x open ∃ y � = x y ∈ U x ∩ A . Fact. If ( X , δ ) � GL then X naturally bears a topology τ for which δ = d τ , that is, δ : A �− → d τ ( A ) , for each A ⊆ X . In fact, we can define: A is τ -closed iff δ ( A ) ⊆ A . Equivalently, c ( A ) = A ∪ δ ( A ) is the closure of A .

  22. Scattered spaces Definition (Cantor): X is scattered if every nonempty A ⊆ X has an isolated point. Cantor-Bendixon sequence: � X 0 = X , X α + 1 = d ( X α ) , X λ = X α , if λ is limit . α<λ Notice that all X α are closed and X 0 ⊃ X 1 ⊃ X 2 ⊃ . . . Fact (Cantor): X is scattered ⇐ ⇒ ∃ α : X α = ∅ .

  23. Scattered spaces Definition (Cantor): X is scattered if every nonempty A ⊆ X has an isolated point. Cantor-Bendixon sequence: � X 0 = X , X α + 1 = d ( X α ) , X λ = X α , if λ is limit . α<λ Notice that all X α are closed and X 0 ⊃ X 1 ⊃ X 2 ⊃ . . . Fact (Cantor): X is scattered ⇐ ⇒ ∃ α : X α = ∅ .

  24. Scattered spaces Definition (Cantor): X is scattered if every nonempty A ⊆ X has an isolated point. Cantor-Bendixon sequence: � X 0 = X , X α + 1 = d ( X α ) , X λ = X α , if λ is limit . α<λ Notice that all X α are closed and X 0 ⊃ X 1 ⊃ X 2 ⊃ . . . Fact (Cantor): X is scattered ⇐ ⇒ ∃ α : X α = ∅ .

  25. Examples Left topology τ ≺ on a strict partial ordering ( X , ≺ ) . A ⊆ X is open iff ∀ x , y ( y ≺ x ∈ A ⇒ y ∈ A ) . Fact: ( X , ≺ ) is well-founded iff ( X , τ ≺ ) is scattered. Ordinal Ω with the usual order topology generated by intervals ( α, β ) , [ 0 , β ) , ( α, Ω) such that α < β .

  26. Examples Left topology τ ≺ on a strict partial ordering ( X , ≺ ) . A ⊆ X is open iff ∀ x , y ( y ≺ x ∈ A ⇒ y ∈ A ) . Fact: ( X , ≺ ) is well-founded iff ( X , τ ≺ ) is scattered. Ordinal Ω with the usual order topology generated by intervals ( α, β ) , [ 0 , β ) , ( α, Ω) such that α < β .

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend