topological ramsey theory and the rationals
play

Topological Ramsey Theory and the Rationals Stevo Todorcevic - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Topological Ramsey Theory and the Rationals Stevo Todorcevic Bertinoro, May 23, 2011 Outline 1. Ramsey-classification theory 2. Topological Ramsey spaces 3. The Halpern-L auchli space of strong subtrees 4. Ramsey theory of the countable


  1. An application to Tukey theory For directed sets D and E , put D ≤ T E if there is a cofinal map f : E → D , i.e., a map such that ( ∀ X ⊆ E )[ X cofinal in E ⇒ f [ X ] cofinal in D ] . Let D ≡ T E whenever D ≤ T E and E ≤ T D . Theorem (Tukey, 1940) D ≡ T E holds for directed sets D and E if and only if they are isomorphic to cofinal subsets of a single directed F . We give application to Tukey classification of ultrafilters on N and its relation to the Rudin-Keisler classification . Theorem The following are equivalent for a selective ultrafilter V and an arbitrary nonprincipal ultrafilter U on N : 1. U ≤ T V .

  2. An application to Tukey theory For directed sets D and E , put D ≤ T E if there is a cofinal map f : E → D , i.e., a map such that ( ∀ X ⊆ E )[ X cofinal in E ⇒ f [ X ] cofinal in D ] . Let D ≡ T E whenever D ≤ T E and E ≤ T D . Theorem (Tukey, 1940) D ≡ T E holds for directed sets D and E if and only if they are isomorphic to cofinal subsets of a single directed F . We give application to Tukey classification of ultrafilters on N and its relation to the Rudin-Keisler classification . Theorem The following are equivalent for a selective ultrafilter V and an arbitrary nonprincipal ultrafilter U on N : 1. U ≤ T V . 2. U ≡ RK V α for some countable ordinal α.

  3. Here V α denotes the α th Fubini power of V defined recursively on α up to RK -equivalence in the natural way: A ∈ V α iff { i : { j : 2 i (2 j + 1) ∈ A } ∈ V α i } ∈ V where α i = α − 1 for all i when α is successor or α i ↑ α when α is a limit ordinal.

  4. Here V α denotes the α th Fubini power of V defined recursively on α up to RK -equivalence in the natural way: A ∈ V α iff { i : { j : 2 i (2 j + 1) ∈ A } ∈ V α i } ∈ V where α i = α − 1 for all i when α is successor or α i ↑ α when α is a limit ordinal. Lemma V ≡ T V α for every selective ultrafilter V and every countable ordinal α > 0 .

  5. Here V α denotes the α th Fubini power of V defined recursively on α up to RK -equivalence in the natural way: A ∈ V α iff { i : { j : 2 i (2 j + 1) ∈ A } ∈ V α i } ∈ V where α i = α − 1 for all i when α is successor or α i ↑ α when α is a limit ordinal. Lemma V ≡ T V α for every selective ultrafilter V and every countable ordinal α > 0 . Corollary The following are equivalent for two selective ultrafilters U and V : 1. U ≤ T V . 2. U ≤ RK V .

  6. Here V α denotes the α th Fubini power of V defined recursively on α up to RK -equivalence in the natural way: A ∈ V α iff { i : { j : 2 i (2 j + 1) ∈ A } ∈ V α i } ∈ V where α i = α − 1 for all i when α is successor or α i ↑ α when α is a limit ordinal. Lemma V ≡ T V α for every selective ultrafilter V and every countable ordinal α > 0 . Corollary The following are equivalent for two selective ultrafilters U and V : 1. U ≤ T V . 2. U ≤ RK V . Corollary Selective ultrafilters realize minimal cofinal types in β N \ N .

  7. Ultrafilters on barriers For a barrier B and n ∈ N , set B { n } = { s \ { n } : s ∈ B , n = min ( s ) } . Then B { n } is a barrier on N \ { 0 , 1 ...., n } for all n ∈ N .

  8. Ultrafilters on barriers For a barrier B and n ∈ N , set B { n } = { s \ { n } : s ∈ B , n = min ( s ) } . Then B { n } is a barrier on N \ { 0 , 1 ...., n } for all n ∈ N . Fix a nonprincipal ultrafilter U on N . Define an ultrafilter U B on B as follows: X ∈ U B ⇔ ( U n ) X { n } ∈ U B { n } .

  9. Ultrafilters on barriers For a barrier B and n ∈ N , set B { n } = { s \ { n } : s ∈ B , n = min ( s ) } . Then B { n } is a barrier on N \ { 0 , 1 ...., n } for all n ∈ N . Fix a nonprincipal ultrafilter U on N . Define an ultrafilter U B on B as follows: X ∈ U B ⇔ ( U n ) X { n } ∈ U B { n } . Example If B = [ N ] k for some positive integer k then U k = U [ N ] k is the usual k th Fubini power of U .

  10. Ultrafilters on barriers For a barrier B and n ∈ N , set B { n } = { s \ { n } : s ∈ B , n = min ( s ) } . Then B { n } is a barrier on N \ { 0 , 1 ...., n } for all n ∈ N . Fix a nonprincipal ultrafilter U on N . Define an ultrafilter U B on B as follows: X ∈ U B ⇔ ( U n ) X { n } ∈ U B { n } . Example If B = [ N ] k for some positive integer k then U k = U [ N ] k is the usual k th Fubini power of U . The ultrafilters of the form U B for B a barrier on N will be called the countable Fubini powers of the ultrafilter U .

  11. Suppose U ≤ T V and that V is selective. Fix a cofinal map f : V → U .

  12. Suppose U ≤ T V and that V is selective. Fix a cofinal map f : V → U . Step 1: Show that f can be assumed to be continuous or more precisely that f = h ↾ V for some continuous h : N [ ∞ ] → 2 N .

  13. Suppose U ≤ T V and that V is selective. Fix a cofinal map f : V → U . Step 1: Show that f can be assumed to be continuous or more precisely that f = h ↾ V for some continuous h : N [ ∞ ] → 2 N . Step 2: Consider the corresponding h 1 : N [ ∞ ] → N defined by h 1 ( M ) = min( h ( M )) .

  14. Suppose U ≤ T V and that V is selective. Fix a cofinal map f : V → U . Step 1: Show that f can be assumed to be continuous or more precisely that f = h ↾ V for some continuous h : N [ ∞ ] → 2 N . Step 2: Consider the corresponding h 1 : N [ ∞ ] → N defined by h 1 ( M ) = min( h ( M )) . Then there is a barrier B on N and g : B → N such that h 1 ( M ) = g ( t M ) , where t M is the unique t ∈ B such that t ⊑ M .

  15. Suppose U ≤ T V and that V is selective. Fix a cofinal map f : V → U . Step 1: Show that f can be assumed to be continuous or more precisely that f = h ↾ V for some continuous h : N [ ∞ ] → 2 N . Step 2: Consider the corresponding h 1 : N [ ∞ ] → N defined by h 1 ( M ) = min( h ( M )) . Then there is a barrier B on N and g : B → N such that h 1 ( M ) = g ( t M ) , where t M is the unique t ∈ B such that t ⊑ M . Step 3: Find M ∈ V and irreducible map ϕ : B → N such that E g ↾ ( B ↾ M ) = E ϕ ↾ ( B ↾ M ) .

  16. Suppose U ≤ T V and that V is selective. Fix a cofinal map f : V → U . Step 1: Show that f can be assumed to be continuous or more precisely that f = h ↾ V for some continuous h : N [ ∞ ] → 2 N . Step 2: Consider the corresponding h 1 : N [ ∞ ] → N defined by h 1 ( M ) = min( h ( M )) . Then there is a barrier B on N and g : B → N such that h 1 ( M ) = g ( t M ) , where t M is the unique t ∈ B such that t ⊑ M . Step 3: Find M ∈ V and irreducible map ϕ : B → N such that E g ↾ ( B ↾ M ) = E ϕ ↾ ( B ↾ M ) . Step 4: Show that this means that U ≡ RK V ϕ [ B ] .

  17. Topological Ramsey spaces A topological Ramsey space is a set R of sequences A = ( a k ) of objects and a quasi-ordering ≤ which defines the corresponding topology of basic-open sets of the form [ n , B ] = { A ∈ R : A ≤ B and a k = b k for all n < k } with the property that all Baire subsets X of R are Ramsey , i.e., ( ∀ n < ω )( ∀ B ∈ R )( ∃ A ∈ [ n , B ])[[ n , A ] ⊆ X or [ n , A ] ∩ X = ∅ ] .

  18. Topological Ramsey spaces A topological Ramsey space is a set R of sequences A = ( a k ) of objects and a quasi-ordering ≤ which defines the corresponding topology of basic-open sets of the form [ n , B ] = { A ∈ R : A ≤ B and a k = b k for all n < k } with the property that all Baire subsets X of R are Ramsey , i.e., ( ∀ n < ω )( ∀ B ∈ R )( ∃ A ∈ [ n , B ])[[ n , A ] ⊆ X or [ n , A ] ∩ X = ∅ ] . Notation: r n ( A ) = � a k : k < n � is the n th approximation to A . AR is the collection of all approximations to sequences in R . | a | is the length of an approximation a ∈ AR . AR l = { a ∈ AR : | a | = l } . [ a , B ] = { A ∈ R : A ≤ B and r | a | ( A ) = a } .

  19. A sufficient condition for R being a topological Ramsey space is that R is a closed subset of AR ω . and that the triple ( R , ≤ , r ) has the following properties:

  20. A sufficient condition for R being a topological Ramsey space is that R is a closed subset of AR ω . and that the triple ( R , ≤ , r ) has the following properties: A.1. Finitization There is a quasi-ordering ≤ fin on AR such that (1) { a ∈ AR : a ≤ fin b } is finite for all b ∈ AR , (2) A ≤ B iff ( ∀ n )( ∃ m ) r n ( A ) ≤ fin r m ( B ) , (3) ∀ a , b ∈ AR [ a ⊑ b ∧ b ≤ fin c → ∃ d ⊑ c a ≤ fin d ] .

  21. A sufficient condition for R being a topological Ramsey space is that R is a closed subset of AR ω . and that the triple ( R , ≤ , r ) has the following properties: A.1. Finitization There is a quasi-ordering ≤ fin on AR such that (1) { a ∈ AR : a ≤ fin b } is finite for all b ∈ AR , (2) A ≤ B iff ( ∀ n )( ∃ m ) r n ( A ) ≤ fin r m ( B ) , (3) ∀ a , b ∈ AR [ a ⊑ b ∧ b ≤ fin c → ∃ d ⊑ c a ≤ fin d ] . A.2. Amalgamation (1) If depth B ( a ) < ∞ then [ a , A ] � = ∅ for all A ∈ [ depth B ( a ) , B ]. (2) A ≤ B and [ a , A ] � = ∅ imply that there is A ′ ∈ [ depth B ( a ) , B ] such that ∅ � = [ a , A ′ ] ⊆ [ a , A ].

  22. A sufficient condition for R being a topological Ramsey space is that R is a closed subset of AR ω . and that the triple ( R , ≤ , r ) has the following properties: A.1. Finitization There is a quasi-ordering ≤ fin on AR such that (1) { a ∈ AR : a ≤ fin b } is finite for all b ∈ AR , (2) A ≤ B iff ( ∀ n )( ∃ m ) r n ( A ) ≤ fin r m ( B ) , (3) ∀ a , b ∈ AR [ a ⊑ b ∧ b ≤ fin c → ∃ d ⊑ c a ≤ fin d ] . A.2. Amalgamation (1) If depth B ( a ) < ∞ then [ a , A ] � = ∅ for all A ∈ [ depth B ( a ) , B ]. (2) A ≤ B and [ a , A ] � = ∅ imply that there is A ′ ∈ [ depth B ( a ) , B ] such that ∅ � = [ a , A ′ ] ⊆ [ a , A ]. A.3. Pigeon-Hole If depth B ( a ) < ∞ and if O ⊆ AR | a | +1 , then there is A ∈ [ depth B ( a ) , B ] such that r | a | +1 [ a , A ] ⊆ O or r | a | +1 [ a , A ] ⊆ O c .

  23. The Ramsey-Galvin-Prikry-Ellentuck space Let R = N [ ∞ ] = { A ⊆ N : | A | = ℵ 0 } , ≤ = ⊆ , and r n ( A ) = { first n members of A } .

  24. The Ramsey-Galvin-Prikry-Ellentuck space Let R = N [ ∞ ] = { A ⊆ N : | A | = ℵ 0 } , ≤ = ⊆ , and r n ( A ) = { first n members of A } . Theorem (Ellentuck, 1974) N [ ∞ ] is a topological Ramsey space.

  25. The Ramsey-Galvin-Prikry-Ellentuck space Let R = N [ ∞ ] = { A ⊆ N : | A | = ℵ 0 } , ≤ = ⊆ , and r n ( A ) = { first n members of A } . Theorem (Ellentuck, 1974) N [ ∞ ] is a topological Ramsey space. Theorem (Galvin-Prikry, 1973) For every finite Borel coloring of N [ ∞ ] there is infinite M ⊆ N such that M [ ∞ ] is monochromatic.

  26. The Ramsey-Galvin-Prikry-Ellentuck space Let R = N [ ∞ ] = { A ⊆ N : | A | = ℵ 0 } , ≤ = ⊆ , and r n ( A ) = { first n members of A } . Theorem (Ellentuck, 1974) N [ ∞ ] is a topological Ramsey space. Theorem (Galvin-Prikry, 1973) For every finite Borel coloring of N [ ∞ ] there is infinite M ⊆ N such that M [ ∞ ] is monochromatic. Theorem (Erd˝ os-Rado, 1950) For every positive integer k and every equivalence relation ∼ on N [ k ] there is I ⊆ k and infinite M ⊆ N such that for a , b ∈ N [ k ] , a ∼ b iff ( ∀ i ∈ I ) a i = b i .

  27. The Ramsey-Galvin-Prikry-Ellentuck space Let R = N [ ∞ ] = { A ⊆ N : | A | = ℵ 0 } , ≤ = ⊆ , and r n ( A ) = { first n members of A } . Theorem (Ellentuck, 1974) N [ ∞ ] is a topological Ramsey space. Theorem (Galvin-Prikry, 1973) For every finite Borel coloring of N [ ∞ ] there is infinite M ⊆ N such that M [ ∞ ] is monochromatic. Theorem (Erd˝ os-Rado, 1950) For every positive integer k and every equivalence relation ∼ on N [ k ] there is I ⊆ k and infinite M ⊆ N such that for a , b ∈ N [ k ] , a ∼ b iff ( ∀ i ∈ I ) a i = b i . Theorem (Ramsey, 1930) For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of N [ k ] there is infinite M ⊆ N such that M [ k ] is monochromatic.

  28. The Halpern-L¨ auchli space of strong subtrees

  29. The Halpern-L¨ auchli space of strong subtrees Let U be a fixed rooted finitely branching tree of height ω with no terminal nodes and we study its subtrees. We assume U ⊆ ω <ω .

  30. The Halpern-L¨ auchli space of strong subtrees Let U be a fixed rooted finitely branching tree of height ω with no terminal nodes and we study its subtrees. We assume U ⊆ ω <ω . We say that T is a strong subtree of U if T is also rooted and if there is A = { n i } ⊆ ω, the level-set of T , such that

  31. The Halpern-L¨ auchli space of strong subtrees Let U be a fixed rooted finitely branching tree of height ω with no terminal nodes and we study its subtrees. We assume U ⊆ ω <ω . We say that T is a strong subtree of U if T is also rooted and if there is A = { n i } ⊆ ω, the level-set of T , such that (1) the i th level T ( i ) of the tree T is a subset of the n i th level U ( n i ) of the tree U ,

  32. The Halpern-L¨ auchli space of strong subtrees Let U be a fixed rooted finitely branching tree of height ω with no terminal nodes and we study its subtrees. We assume U ⊆ ω <ω . We say that T is a strong subtree of U if T is also rooted and if there is A = { n i } ⊆ ω, the level-set of T , such that (1) the i th level T ( i ) of the tree T is a subset of the n i th level U ( n i ) of the tree U , (2) if m < n are two successive elements of the set A , then for every s ∈ T ∩ U ( m ) , every immediate successor of s in U has exactly one extension in T ∩ U ( n ) .

  33. The Halpern-L¨ auchli space of strong subtrees Let U be a fixed rooted finitely branching tree of height ω with no terminal nodes and we study its subtrees. We assume U ⊆ ω <ω . We say that T is a strong subtree of U if T is also rooted and if there is A = { n i } ⊆ ω, the level-set of T , such that (1) the i th level T ( i ) of the tree T is a subset of the n i th level U ( n i ) of the tree U , (2) if m < n are two successive elements of the set A , then for every s ∈ T ∩ U ( m ) , every immediate successor of s in U has exactly one extension in T ∩ U ( n ) . S k ( U ) = the collection of all strong subtrees of U of height k .

  34. The Halpern-L¨ auchli space of strong subtrees Let U be a fixed rooted finitely branching tree of height ω with no terminal nodes and we study its subtrees. We assume U ⊆ ω <ω . We say that T is a strong subtree of U if T is also rooted and if there is A = { n i } ⊆ ω, the level-set of T , such that (1) the i th level T ( i ) of the tree T is a subset of the n i th level U ( n i ) of the tree U , (2) if m < n are two successive elements of the set A , then for every s ∈ T ∩ U ( m ) , every immediate successor of s in U has exactly one extension in T ∩ U ( n ) . S k ( U ) = the collection of all strong subtrees of U of height k . Theorem (Milliken, 1981) S ω ( U ) is a topological Ramsey space.

  35. The Halpern-L¨ auchli space of strong subtrees Let U be a fixed rooted finitely branching tree of height ω with no terminal nodes and we study its subtrees. We assume U ⊆ ω <ω . We say that T is a strong subtree of U if T is also rooted and if there is A = { n i } ⊆ ω, the level-set of T , such that (1) the i th level T ( i ) of the tree T is a subset of the n i th level U ( n i ) of the tree U , (2) if m < n are two successive elements of the set A , then for every s ∈ T ∩ U ( m ) , every immediate successor of s in U has exactly one extension in T ∩ U ( n ) . S k ( U ) = the collection of all strong subtrees of U of height k . Theorem (Milliken, 1981) S ω ( U ) is a topological Ramsey space. Corollary For every finite Borel coloring of S ω ( U ) there is a strong subtree T of U of height ω such that S ω ( T ) is monochromatic.

  36. Corollary For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of S k ( U ) there is T ∈ S ω ( U ) such that S k ( T ) is monochromatic.

  37. Corollary For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of S k ( U ) there is T ∈ S ω ( U ) such that S k ( T ) is monochromatic. Corollary For every equivalence relation ∼ on U there is a strong subtree T of U of height ω such that one of the following holds: 1. ( ∀ s , t ∈ T )[ s ∼ t ⇔ s = t ] , 2. ( ∀ s , t ∈ T )[ s ∼ t ⇔ s = s ] , 3. ( ∀ s , t ∈ T )[ s ∼ t ⇔ | s | = | t | ] ,

  38. Corollary For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of S k ( U ) there is T ∈ S ω ( U ) such that S k ( T ) is monochromatic. Corollary For every equivalence relation ∼ on U there is a strong subtree T of U of height ω such that one of the following holds: 1. ( ∀ s , t ∈ T )[ s ∼ t ⇔ s = t ] , 2. ( ∀ s , t ∈ T )[ s ∼ t ⇔ s = s ] , 3. ( ∀ s , t ∈ T )[ s ∼ t ⇔ | s | = | t | ] , Corollary U contains a strong subtree S of height ω such that either 1. S is uniformly branching of some degree d 2. nodes of S of the same height have the same degree which increase as the height increase 3. different nodes of S have different branching degrees.

  39. Fix a positive integer d and consider the tree U d = d <ω with the usual end-extension ordering ⊑ and the lexicographical ordering.

  40. Fix a positive integer d and consider the tree U d = d <ω with the usual end-extension ordering ⊑ and the lexicographical ordering. Then every pair of strong subtrees A and B of U of some fixed height k are isomorphic as they are isomorphic to d < k . Note that there is a unique isomorphism preserving the lexicographical ordering. We shall use only about this kind of isomorphisms.

  41. Fix a positive integer d and consider the tree U d = d <ω with the usual end-extension ordering ⊑ and the lexicographical ordering. Then every pair of strong subtrees A and B of U of some fixed height k are isomorphic as they are isomorphic to d < k . Note that there is a unique isomorphism preserving the lexicographical ordering. We shall use only about this kind of isomorphisms. Theorem (Milliken, 1980) For every positive integer k and every equivalence relation ∼ on S k ( U d ) there is a strong subtree T of U d and a pair ( N , L ) ∈ P ( d < k ) × P ( k ) with max {| s | : s ∈ N } < min( L ) such that A , B ∈ S k ( T ) , we have that A ∼ B iff

  42. Fix a positive integer d and consider the tree U d = d <ω with the usual end-extension ordering ⊑ and the lexicographical ordering. Then every pair of strong subtrees A and B of U of some fixed height k are isomorphic as they are isomorphic to d < k . Note that there is a unique isomorphism preserving the lexicographical ordering. We shall use only about this kind of isomorphisms. Theorem (Milliken, 1980) For every positive integer k and every equivalence relation ∼ on S k ( U d ) there is a strong subtree T of U d and a pair ( N , L ) ∈ P ( d < k ) × P ( k ) with max {| s | : s ∈ N } < min( L ) such that A , B ∈ S k ( T ) , we have that A ∼ B iff (1) the isomorphisms between d < k and A and B agree on N ,

  43. Fix a positive integer d and consider the tree U d = d <ω with the usual end-extension ordering ⊑ and the lexicographical ordering. Then every pair of strong subtrees A and B of U of some fixed height k are isomorphic as they are isomorphic to d < k . Note that there is a unique isomorphism preserving the lexicographical ordering. We shall use only about this kind of isomorphisms. Theorem (Milliken, 1980) For every positive integer k and every equivalence relation ∼ on S k ( U d ) there is a strong subtree T of U d and a pair ( N , L ) ∈ P ( d < k ) × P ( k ) with max {| s | : s ∈ N } < min( L ) such that A , B ∈ S k ( T ) , we have that A ∼ B iff (1) the isomorphisms between d < k and A and B agree on N , (2) for l ∈ L , the l-th levels of A and B are subsets of the same level of T .

  44. The countable dense linear ordering

  45. The countable dense linear ordering Theorem (Devlin-Laver 1979) For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that [ P ] k uses at most t k colors. Here, t k = � k − 1 � 2 k − 2 � t l · t k − l is the standard sequence of odd l =1 2 l − 1 tangent numbers: t 1 = 1 , t 2 = 2 , t 3 = 16 , etc.

  46. The countable dense linear ordering Theorem (Devlin-Laver 1979) For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that [ P ] k uses at most t k colors. Here, t k = � k − 1 � 2 k − 2 � t l · t k − l is the standard sequence of odd l =1 2 l − 1 tangent numbers: t 1 = 1 , t 2 = 2 , t 3 = 16 , etc. We apply the strong-subtree Ramsey theorem for U = 2 <ω and after getting monochromatic T ∈ S ω ( U ) we consider the subtree that corresponds to the following: Let S be the ∧ -closed subtree of 2 <ω uniquely determined by the following properties:

  47. The countable dense linear ordering Theorem (Devlin-Laver 1979) For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that [ P ] k uses at most t k colors. Here, t k = � k − 1 � 2 k − 2 � t l · t k − l is the standard sequence of odd l =1 2 l − 1 tangent numbers: t 1 = 1 , t 2 = 2 , t 3 = 16 , etc. We apply the strong-subtree Ramsey theorem for U = 2 <ω and after getting monochromatic T ∈ S ω ( U ) we consider the subtree that corresponds to the following: Let S be the ∧ -closed subtree of 2 <ω uniquely determined by the following properties: (1) root ( S ) = ∅ and S is isomorphic to 2 <ω ,

  48. The countable dense linear ordering Theorem (Devlin-Laver 1979) For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that [ P ] k uses at most t k colors. Here, t k = � k − 1 � 2 k − 2 � t l · t k − l is the standard sequence of odd l =1 2 l − 1 tangent numbers: t 1 = 1 , t 2 = 2 , t 3 = 16 , etc. We apply the strong-subtree Ramsey theorem for U = 2 <ω and after getting monochromatic T ∈ S ω ( U ) we consider the subtree that corresponds to the following: Let S be the ∧ -closed subtree of 2 <ω uniquely determined by the following properties: (1) root ( S ) = ∅ and S is isomorphic to 2 <ω , (2) | S ∩ 2 3 n | = 1 and S ∩ 2 3 n +1 = S ∩ 2 3 n +2 = ∅ for all n ,

  49. The countable dense linear ordering Theorem (Devlin-Laver 1979) For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that [ P ] k uses at most t k colors. Here, t k = � k − 1 � 2 k − 2 � t l · t k − l is the standard sequence of odd l =1 2 l − 1 tangent numbers: t 1 = 1 , t 2 = 2 , t 3 = 16 , etc. We apply the strong-subtree Ramsey theorem for U = 2 <ω and after getting monochromatic T ∈ S ω ( U ) we consider the subtree that corresponds to the following: Let S be the ∧ -closed subtree of 2 <ω uniquely determined by the following properties: (1) root ( S ) = ∅ and S is isomorphic to 2 <ω , (2) | S ∩ 2 3 n | = 1 and S ∩ 2 3 n +1 = S ∩ 2 3 n +2 = ∅ for all n , (3) ( ∀ m )( ∀ s , t ∈ S ( m ))( s < lex t ⇒ | s | < | t | ),

  50. The countable dense linear ordering Theorem (Devlin-Laver 1979) For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that [ P ] k uses at most t k colors. Here, t k = � k − 1 � 2 k − 2 � t l · t k − l is the standard sequence of odd l =1 2 l − 1 tangent numbers: t 1 = 1 , t 2 = 2 , t 3 = 16 , etc. We apply the strong-subtree Ramsey theorem for U = 2 <ω and after getting monochromatic T ∈ S ω ( U ) we consider the subtree that corresponds to the following: Let S be the ∧ -closed subtree of 2 <ω uniquely determined by the following properties: (1) root ( S ) = ∅ and S is isomorphic to 2 <ω , (2) | S ∩ 2 3 n | = 1 and S ∩ 2 3 n +1 = S ∩ 2 3 n +2 = ∅ for all n , (3) ( ∀ m )( ∀ s , t ∈ S ( m ))( s < lex t ⇒ | s | < | t | ), (4) ( ∀ m < n )( ∀ s ∈ S ( m ))( ∀ t ∈ S ( n )) | s | < | t | ,

  51. The countable dense linear ordering Theorem (Devlin-Laver 1979) For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that [ P ] k uses at most t k colors. Here, t k = � k − 1 � 2 k − 2 � t l · t k − l is the standard sequence of odd l =1 2 l − 1 tangent numbers: t 1 = 1 , t 2 = 2 , t 3 = 16 , etc. We apply the strong-subtree Ramsey theorem for U = 2 <ω and after getting monochromatic T ∈ S ω ( U ) we consider the subtree that corresponds to the following: Let S be the ∧ -closed subtree of 2 <ω uniquely determined by the following properties: (1) root ( S ) = ∅ and S is isomorphic to 2 <ω , (2) | S ∩ 2 3 n | = 1 and S ∩ 2 3 n +1 = S ∩ 2 3 n +2 = ∅ for all n , (3) ( ∀ m )( ∀ s , t ∈ S ( m ))( s < lex t ⇒ | s | < | t | ), (4) ( ∀ m < n )( ∀ s ∈ S ( m ))( ∀ t ∈ S ( n )) | s | < | t | , (5) ( ∀ s ∈ S )( ∀ t �∈ S )( t ⊑ s ⇒ t ⌢ (0) ⊑ s ) .

  52. Ramsey-classification problem for [ Q ] k

  53. Ramsey-classification problem for [ Q ] k Theorem (Vuksanovic, 2003) For every positive integer k the class of all equivalence relations on the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q has a Ramsey basis of equivalence relations E T determined by ’transitive sets’ T ⊆ [2 ≤ 4 k − 2 ] × [2 ≤ 4 k − 2 ] . In case k = 1 the Ramsey basis has 2 elements and in case k = 2 it has 57 elements.

  54. Ramsey-classification problem for [ Q ] k Theorem (Vuksanovic, 2003) For every positive integer k the class of all equivalence relations on the set [ Q ] k of all k-element subsets of Q has a Ramsey basis of equivalence relations E T determined by ’transitive sets’ T ⊆ [2 ≤ 4 k − 2 ] × [2 ≤ 4 k − 2 ] . In case k = 1 the Ramsey basis has 2 elements and in case k = 2 it has 57 elements. Remark The exact size of an irredundant Ramsey basis of the class of equivalence relations on [ Q ] 3 is not known.

  55. Theorem The set Q [ ∞ ] of infinite of rapidly increasing sequences of rational numbers is a Ramsey space.

  56. Theorem The set Q [ ∞ ] of infinite of rapidly increasing sequences of rational numbers is a Ramsey space. Corollary For every finite Borel coloring of Q [ ∞ ] there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that P [ ∞ ] is monochromatic.

  57. Theorem The set Q [ ∞ ] of infinite of rapidly increasing sequences of rational numbers is a Ramsey space. Corollary For every finite Borel coloring of Q [ ∞ ] there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that P [ ∞ ] is monochromatic. Corollary For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set Q [ k ] of rapidly increasing k-sequences of elements of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that P [ k ] is monochromatic.

  58. Theorem The set Q [ ∞ ] of infinite of rapidly increasing sequences of rational numbers is a Ramsey space. Corollary For every finite Borel coloring of Q [ ∞ ] there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that P [ ∞ ] is monochromatic. Corollary For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of the set Q [ k ] of rapidly increasing k-sequences of elements of Q there is P ⊆ Q order-isomorphic to Q such that P [ k ] is monochromatic. Theorem For every positive integer k the collection of equivalence relations on Q [ k ] has a finite Ramsey basis of cardinality h k = 2 � k i =0 5 i .

  59. The Hindman-Milliken-Taylor space FIN [ ∞ ]

  60. The Hindman-Milliken-Taylor space FIN [ ∞ ] We work with the the countable dense-in-itself metric space Q = {∅} ∪ FIN ⊆ 2 N , where FIN is the collection of all finite nonempty subsets of N .

  61. The Hindman-Milliken-Taylor space FIN [ ∞ ] We work with the the countable dense-in-itself metric space Q = {∅} ∪ FIN ⊆ 2 N , where FIN is the collection of all finite nonempty subsets of N . Theorem (Milliken, 1975) The collection FIN [ ∞ ] of all infinite sequences of elements of FIN converging to ∅ is a topological Ramsey space.

  62. The Hindman-Milliken-Taylor space FIN [ ∞ ] We work with the the countable dense-in-itself metric space Q = {∅} ∪ FIN ⊆ 2 N , where FIN is the collection of all finite nonempty subsets of N . Theorem (Milliken, 1975) The collection FIN [ ∞ ] of all infinite sequences of elements of FIN converging to ∅ is a topological Ramsey space. If X = ( x n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] then max( x m ) < min( x n ) whenever m < n and for X = ( x n ) , Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] , we set X ≤ Y whenever X ⊆ [ Y ] , where [ Y ] = { y n 0 ∪ · · · y n k : n 0 < · · · < n k } .

  63. Corollary For every finite Borel coloring of FIN [ ∞ ] there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] such that [ Y ] [ ∞ ] is monochromatic.

  64. Corollary For every finite Borel coloring of FIN [ ∞ ] there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] such that [ Y ] [ ∞ ] is monochromatic. Corollary For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of FIN [ k ] there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] such that [ Y ] [ k ] is monochromatic.

  65. Corollary For every finite Borel coloring of FIN [ ∞ ] there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] such that [ Y ] [ ∞ ] is monochromatic. Corollary For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of FIN [ k ] there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] such that [ Y ] [ k ] is monochromatic. Theorem (Taylor, 1976) For every equivalence relation E on FIN there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] and ϕ ∈ { const , ident , min , max , (min , max) } such that E ↾ [ Y ] = E ϕ ↾ [ Y ] .

  66. Corollary For every finite Borel coloring of FIN [ ∞ ] there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] such that [ Y ] [ ∞ ] is monochromatic. Corollary For every positive integer k and every finite coloring of FIN [ k ] there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] such that [ Y ] [ k ] is monochromatic. Theorem (Taylor, 1976) For every equivalence relation E on FIN there is Y = ( y n ) ∈ FIN [ ∞ ] and ϕ ∈ { const , ident , min , max , (min , max) } such that E ↾ [ Y ] = E ϕ ↾ [ Y ] . Theorem (Lefmann, 1996) For every positive integer k the class of equivalence relations on FIN [ k ] has a Ramsey basis of cardinality √ √ √ √ 13) k + (13 − 3 1 13) k ] . 13)(7 − s k = 13 · 2 k +1 [(13 + 3 13)(7 +

  67. Ramsey on countable topological spaces

  68. Ramsey on countable topological spaces Theorem (Baumgartner, 1986) Suppose X is a countable Hausdorff topological space. Then there is c : [ X ] 2 → ω such that c [ P ] 2 ⊇ { 0 , 1 , ..., 2 n − 1 } for all n < ω and all P ⊆ X such that P ( n ) � = ∅ Here P (0) = P , P ( n +1) = ( P ( n ) ) ′ , where for a subset A of X we let A ′ = { x ∈ A : x ∈ A \ { x }} .

  69. Ramsey on countable topological spaces Theorem (Baumgartner, 1986) Suppose X is a countable Hausdorff topological space. Then there is c : [ X ] 2 → ω such that c [ P ] 2 ⊇ { 0 , 1 , ..., 2 n − 1 } for all n < ω and all P ⊆ X such that P ( n ) � = ∅ Here P (0) = P , P ( n +1) = ( P ( n ) ) ′ , where for a subset A of X we let A ′ = { x ∈ A : x ∈ A \ { x }} . Theorem (Baumgartner, 1986) For every positive integer n and every finite coloring of [ ε 0 ] 2 there is P ⊆ ε 0 order-homeomorphic to ω n + 1 such that [ P ] 2 uses no more than 2 n colors.

  70. FIN as a topological copy of Q

  71. FIN as a topological copy of Q Recall that FIN is the space of all finite nonempty subsets of N and we shall take it with the topology induced from 2 N as our topological copy of the rationals Q .

  72. FIN as a topological copy of Q Recall that FIN is the space of all finite nonempty subsets of N and we shall take it with the topology induced from 2 N as our topological copy of the rationals Q . For X ⊆ Q , let ∂ 0 ( X ) = X and ∂ k +1 ( X ) = ∂ ( ∂ k ( X )) , where ∂ ( X ) = { x ∈ Q : x ∈ X \ { x }} . Thus X ′ = ∂ ( X ) ∩ X so the two derivatives agree on closed subsets of Q .

  73. FIN as a topological copy of Q Recall that FIN is the space of all finite nonempty subsets of N and we shall take it with the topology induced from 2 N as our topological copy of the rationals Q . For X ⊆ Q , let ∂ 0 ( X ) = X and ∂ k +1 ( X ) = ∂ ( ∂ k ( X )) , where ∂ ( X ) = { x ∈ Q : x ∈ X \ { x }} . Thus X ′ = ∂ ( X ) ∩ X so the two derivatives agree on closed subsets of Q . Theorem For every positive integers k and n there is integer h ( n , k ) such that for every finite coloring of [ Q ] k there is P ⊆ Q homeomorphic to ω n such that [ P ] k uses at most h ( k , n ) colors.

  74. FIN as a topological copy of Q Recall that FIN is the space of all finite nonempty subsets of N and we shall take it with the topology induced from 2 N as our topological copy of the rationals Q . For X ⊆ Q , let ∂ 0 ( X ) = X and ∂ k +1 ( X ) = ∂ ( ∂ k ( X )) , where ∂ ( X ) = { x ∈ Q : x ∈ X \ { x }} . Thus X ′ = ∂ ( X ) ∩ X so the two derivatives agree on closed subsets of Q . Theorem For every positive integers k and n there is integer h ( n , k ) such that for every finite coloring of [ Q ] k there is P ⊆ Q homeomorphic to ω n such that [ P ] k uses at most h ( k , n ) colors. Remark The function seems expressible using the standard enumerating functions. For example, h ( n , 2) = 2 n for all n .

  75. The oscillation mapping

  76. The oscillation mapping The oscillation mapping on Q = {∅} ∪ FIN ⊆ 2 N : Define osc : Q 2 → ω by osc ( s , t ) = | ( s △ t ) / ∼ | , where for i , j ∈ s △ t , we let i ∼ j iff [ i , j ] ∩ ( s \ t ) = ∅ or [ i , j ] ∩ ( t \ s ) = ∅ .

  77. The oscillation mapping The oscillation mapping on Q = {∅} ∪ FIN ⊆ 2 N : Define osc : Q 2 → ω by osc ( s , t ) = | ( s △ t ) / ∼ | , where for i , j ∈ s △ t , we let i ∼ j iff [ i , j ] ∩ ( s \ t ) = ∅ or [ i , j ] ∩ ( t \ s ) = ∅ . Proposition Suppose that ∂ k ( X ) � = ∅ for some X ⊆ Q and some positive integer k . then osc [ X 2 ] ⊇ { 2 , 3 , ..., 2 k } . If, moreover, X ∩ ∂ ( X ) � = ∅ then 1 ∈ osc [ X 2 ] as well.

  78. Corollary The class of equivalence relations on the square of the countable dense-in-itself metric space has no finite (and, in fact, no countable) Ramsey basis.

  79. Corollary The class of equivalence relations on the square of the countable dense-in-itself metric space has no finite (and, in fact, no countable) Ramsey basis. However, the following fact shows that the oscillation mapping is in some sense canonical . Proposition For every f : [ Q ] 2 → ω and every positive integer n there is X ⊆ Q homeomorphic to Q such that for { s , t } , { s ′ , t ′ } ∈ [ X ] 2 , osc ( s , t ) = osc ( s ′ , t ′ ) implies f ( s , t ) = f ( s ′ , t ′ ) provided that the numbers f ( s , t ) , f ( s ′ , t ′ ) , osc ( s , t ) and osc ( s ′ , t ′ ) are all ≤ n .

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend