strict ideal completions of the lambda calculus
play

Strict Ideal Completions of the Lambda Calculus Patrick Bahr IT - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Strict Ideal Completions of the Lambda Calculus Patrick Bahr IT University of Copenhagen FSCD 2018 Infinitary Lambda Calculus N N y N y y . . . where N = ( x . x x y )( x . x x y ) 1 / 13 Infinitary Lambda Calculus N N


  1. Strict Ideal Completions of the Lambda Calculus Patrick Bahr IT University of Copenhagen FSCD 2018

  2. Infinitary Lambda Calculus N → N y → N y y → . . . where N = ( λ x . x x y )( λ x . x x y ) 1 / 13

  3. Infinitary Lambda Calculus N → N y → N y y → . . . where N = ( λ x . x x y )( λ x . x x y ) ◮ Can we give a meaningful (infinite) result term for such a non-terminating reduction? 1 / 13

  4. Infinitary Lambda Calculus N → N y → N y y → . . . where N = ( λ x . x x y )( λ x . x x y ) app ◮ Can we give a meaningful app y (infinite) result term for such a non-terminating reduction? app y ◮ How about the infinite term (( . . . y ) y ) y ? y 1 / 13

  5. Infinitary Lambda Calculus N → N y → N y y → . . . where N = ( λ x . x x y )( λ x . x x y ) app ◮ Can we give a meaningful app y (infinite) result term for such a non-terminating reduction? app y ◮ How about the infinite term (( . . . y ) y ) y ? y ◮ There is no single true answer to this question. 1 / 13

  6. Different Infinitary Calculi ◮ Infinite normal forms induce a model of the lambda calculus, e.g. ◮ B¨ ohm Trees, Levy-Longo Trees, Berarducci Trees 2 / 13

  7. Different Infinitary Calculi ◮ Infinite normal forms induce a model of the lambda calculus, e.g. ◮ B¨ ohm Trees, Levy-Longo Trees, Berarducci Trees ◮ In the infinitary lambda calculus corresponding to Berarducci Trees, the reduction N → N y → N y y → . . . converges to (( . . . y ) y ) y ◮ but does not converge in the calculi corresp. to B¨ ohm Trees and Levy-Longo Trees 2 / 13

  8. When do infinite reductions converge? Many variants of infinitary calculi ◮ metric spaces � metric completion ◮ partial orders � ideal completion ◮ topological spaces ◮ coinductive definitions 3 / 13

  9. When do infinite reductions converge? Many variants of infinitary calculi ◮ metric spaces � metric completion ◮ partial orders � ideal completion ◮ topological spaces ◮ coinductive definitions 3 / 13

  10. When do infinite reductions converge? Many variants of infinitary calculi ◮ metric spaces � metric completion ◮ partial orders � ideal completion ◮ topological spaces ◮ coinductive definitions Metric completion approach ◮ adjusting the metric yields different calculi This talk ◮ Can we do the same for partial orders? 3 / 13

  11. Overview 1. Metric Completion 2. Ideal Completion 3. Results

  12. Metric Completion N. Dershowitz, S. Kaplan, D.A. Plaisted. Rewrite, rewrite, rewrite, rewrite, rewrite, ... Theoretical Computer Science, 83(1):71–96, 1991. R. Kennaway, J.W. Klop, M.R. Sleep, and F.-J. de Vries. Infinitary lambda calculus. Theoretical Computer Science, 175(1):93–125, 1997.

  13. Metric on lambda terms Standard metric on terms d ( M , N ) = 2 − d d ( M , M ) = 0 , and if M � = N , where d = minimum depth at which M , N differ 4 / 13

  14. Metric on lambda terms Standard metric on terms d ( M , N ) = 2 − d d ( M , M ) = 0 , and if M � = N , where d = minimum depth at which M , N differ Example d ( λ x . x , x y ) = 2 − 0 = 1 d ( λ x . x , λ x . y ) = 2 − 1 = 1 2 4 / 13

  15. Metric on lambda terms Standard metric on terms d ( M , N ) = 2 − d d ( M , M ) = 0 , and if M � = N , where d = minimum depth at which M , N differ Example d ( λ x . x , x y ) = 2 − 0 = 1 d ( λ x . x , λ x . y ) = 2 − 1 = 1 2 4 / 13

  16. Metric on lambda terms Standard metric on terms d ( M , N ) = 2 − d d ( M , M ) = 0 , and if M � = N , where d = minimum depth at which M , N differ Example d ( λ x . x , x y ) = 2 − 0 = 1 d ( λ x . x , λ x . y ) = 2 − 1 = 1 2 We can manipulate d by changing the notion of depth. 4 / 13

  17. Strictness A triple abc ∈ { 0 , 1 } 3 describes how to measure depth. ◮ a = 1 iff lambda abstraction is counted ◮ b = 1 iff application from the left is counted ◮ c = 1 iff application from the right is counted 5 / 13

  18. Strictness A triple abc ∈ { 0 , 1 } 3 describes how to measure depth. ◮ a = 1 iff lambda abstraction is counted ◮ b = 1 iff application from the left is counted ◮ c = 1 iff application from the right is counted Example d 111 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 2 = 1 / 4 5 / 13

  19. Strictness A triple abc ∈ { 0 , 1 } 3 describes how to measure depth. ◮ a = 1 iff lambda abstraction is counted ◮ b = 1 iff application from the left is counted ◮ c = 1 iff application from the right is counted = standard metric d Example d 111 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 2 = 1 / 4 5 / 13

  20. Strictness A triple abc ∈ { 0 , 1 } 3 describes how to measure depth. ◮ a = 1 iff lambda abstraction is counted ◮ b = 1 iff application from the left is counted ◮ c = 1 iff application from the right is counted Example d 111 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 2 = 1 / 4 d 011 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 1 = 1 / 2 d 001 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 1 = 1 / 2 d 010 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 0 = 1 5 / 13

  21. Strictness A triple abc ∈ { 0 , 1 } 3 describes how to measure depth. ◮ a = 1 iff lambda abstraction is counted ◮ b = 1 iff application from the left is counted ◮ c = 1 iff application from the right is counted Example d 111 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 2 = 1 / 4 d 011 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 1 = 1 / 2 d 001 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 1 = 1 / 2 d 010 ( λ x . x x , λ x . x y ) = 2 − 0 = 1 The infinite term (( . . . y ) y ) y is in the metric completion of d 010 but not d 001 . 5 / 13

  22. Infinitary Lambda Calculus A reduction t 0 → t 1 → t 2 → . . . converges to t iff ◮ depth of contracted redexes tends to infinity, ◮ lim i → ω t i = t . 6 / 13

  23. Infinitary Lambda Calculus A reduction t 0 → t 1 → t 2 → . . . converges to t iff ◮ depth of contracted redexes tends to infinity, ◮ lim i → ω t i = t . B¨ ohm reduction In addition, we need rewrite rules t → ⊥ for each t that is root-active (= can be contracted at depth 0 arbitrarily often) 6 / 13

  24. Properties of the metric completion Theorem ([Kennaway et al.]) ◮ Infinitary B¨ ohm reduction is confluent (for 001 , 101 , and 111 ) and normalising (in general). ◮ Its unique normal forms are B¨ ohm Trees (001), Levy-Longo Trees (101), and Berarducci Trees (111). 7 / 13

  25. Properties of the metric completion Theorem ([Kennaway et al.]) ◮ Infinitary B¨ ohm reduction is confluent (for 001 , 101 , and 111 ) and normalising (in general). ◮ Its unique normal forms are B¨ ohm Trees (001), Levy-Longo Trees (101), and Berarducci Trees (111). Example N → N y → N y y → . . . converges to the infinite term (( . . . y ) y ) y in 111, but not in 001, 101 ((( . . . y ) y ) y is not even a valid term in 001, 101). 7 / 13

  26. Ideal Completion

  27. Partial on lambda terms Standard partial order on terms Least monotone, partial order ≤ ⊥ such that ⊥ ≤ ⊥ M , for any M i.e. M ≤ ⊥ N if N is obtained from M by replacing ⊥ with arbitrary terms 8 / 13

  28. Partial on lambda terms Standard partial order on terms Least monotone, partial order ≤ ⊥ such that ⊥ ≤ ⊥ M , for any M i.e. M ≤ ⊥ N if N is obtained from M by replacing ⊥ with arbitrary terms 8 / 13

  29. Partial on lambda terms Standard partial order on terms Least monotone, partial order ≤ ⊥ such that ⊥ ≤ ⊥ M , for any M i.e. M ≤ ⊥ N if N is obtained from M by replacing ⊥ with arbitrary terms Generalisation to ≤ abc ⊥ ◮ We adjust definition of ≤ ⊥ by restricting monotonicity ◮ For example: λ x . ⊥ �≤ 011 λ x . M . ⊥ 8 / 13

  30. Partial order ≤ abc ⊥ Least partial order ≤ abc such that ⊥ ⊥ ≤ abc M ⊥ λ x . M ≤ abc λ x . M ′ if M ≤ abc M ′ ⊥ ⊥ 9 / 13

  31. Partial order ≤ abc ⊥ Least partial order ≤ abc such that ⊥ ⊥ ≤ abc M ⊥ M ′ and M � = ⊥ or a = 1 λ x . M ≤ abc λ x . M ′ if M ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ 9 / 13

  32. Partial order ≤ abc ⊥ Least partial order ≤ abc such that ⊥ ⊥ ≤ abc M ⊥ M ′ and M � = ⊥ or a = 1 λ x . M ≤ abc λ x . M ′ if M ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ M ′ and M � = ⊥ or b = 1 MN ≤ abc M ′ N if M ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ N ′ and N � = ⊥ or c = 1 MN ′ MN ≤ abc if N ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ 9 / 13

  33. Partial order ≤ abc ⊥ Least partial order ≤ abc such that ⊥ ⊥ ≤ abc M monotonicity ⊥ M ′ and M � = ⊥ or a = 1 λ x . M ≤ abc λ x . M ′ if M ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ M ′ and M � = ⊥ or b = 1 MN ≤ abc M ′ N if M ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ N ′ and N � = ⊥ or c = 1 MN ′ MN ≤ abc if N ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ 9 / 13

  34. Partial order ≤ abc ⊥ Least partial order ≤ abc such that ⊥ ⊥ ≤ abc M monotonicity ⊥ M ′ and M � = ⊥ or a = 1 λ x . M ≤ abc λ x . M ′ if M ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ M ′ and M � = ⊥ or b = 1 MN ≤ abc M ′ N if M ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ N ′ and N � = ⊥ or c = 1 MN ′ MN ≤ abc if N ≤ abc ⊥ ⊥ � ≤ 111 is just the standard partial order ≤ ⊥ ⊥ 9 / 13

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend