seconda universita di napoli
play

Seconda Universita di Napoli Clermont-Ferrand 2006 *joint work with - PDF document

Strong initial segments of models of I 0 Paola DAquino Seconda Universita di Napoli Clermont-Ferrand 2006 *joint work with Julia Knight Language L contains + , , 0 , 1 , < PA : L -theory axiomatized by basic axioms for + and


  1. Strong initial segments of models of I ∆ 0 Paola D’Aquino ∗ Seconda Universita’ di Napoli Clermont-Ferrand 2006 *joint work with Julia Knight

  2. Language L contains + , · , 0 , 1 , < PA : L -theory axiomatized by basic axioms for + and · , and induction ∀ ¯ y (( θ (0 , ¯ y ) ∧ ∀ x ( θ ( x, ¯ y ) → θ ( x + 1 , ¯ y )) → ∀ xθ ( x + 1 , ¯ y )) for any formula θ I ∆ 0 : subsystem of PA where induction is only ∆ 0 -induction ( θ ∈ ∆ 0 ). I ∆ 0 �⊢ expotentiation total (Parikh,71) exp = ∀ x > 1 ∀ y ∃ z ( x y = z ) I ∆ 0 ⊂ I ∆ 0 + exp 1

  3. Defn [ B n formulas] The B 0 formulas are the ∆ 0 formulas. The Σ n +1 formulas have the form ( ∃ u ) ϕ , where ϕ is a B n formula. The B n +1 formulas are obtained from the Σ n +1 formulas by taking Boolean combinations and adding bounded quantifiers. Combinatorial principles are ubiquitous in arith- metical theories, e.g. Ramsey theory, pigeon- hole principle 2

  4. Ramsey Theorem for PA : Let B be a model of PA . Let I be a cofinal definable set, and let F : I [ n ] → c = { 0 , . . . , c − 1 } be a definable partition of I [ n ] , where n is standard and c ∈ B . Then there is a cofinal definable set J ⊆ I that is homogeneous for F . Defn Let I be a subset of an L -structure A . We say that I is diagonal indiscernible for ϕ ( u, x ) if for all i < j, k in I , A | = ( ∀ u ≤ i ) [ ϕ ( u, j ) ↔ ϕ ( u, k )] . Proposition Let A be a model of PA , and let I be a cofinal definable set. For any finite r and any finite set Γ of formulas (with free variables split), there is a set J ⊆ I of size at least r that is diagonal indiscernible for all ϕ ( u, x ) ∈ Γ. Cor. In the same hypothesis get J ⊆ I cofinal definable set of diagonal indiscernible for all ϕ ( u, x ) ∈ Γ. 3

  5. Theorem (McAloon 82) Let M be a model of I ∆ 0 . Then M has a nonstandard initial segment I which is a model of PA The proof uses diagonal indiscernibles Thm. Let A be a model of I ∆ 0 . Let I be a subset of A of order type ω such that = i < j → i 2 < j , 1. for i, j ∈ I , A | 2. I is diagonal indiscernible for all ∆ 0 -formulas. Then B = { x ∈ A : x < i for some i ∈ I } is a model of PA . We want refinements of McAloon’s result 4

  6. Ketonen and Solovay (’81) related the follow- ing three notions: 1. α -largeness 2. Ramsey Theory 3. Wainer functions 5

  7. α -LARGENESS ǫ 0 is the least ordinal α such that ω α = α Cantor normal form: α = ω α 1 x 1 + ω α 2 x 2 + . . . + ω α k x k where α i are ordinals, α 1 > α 2 > . . . > α k and k, x 1 , x 2 , . . . , x k ∈ ω − { 0 } Fundamental sequence: For each ordinal 0 < α < ǫ 0 , we define the x -th ordinal in the fundamental sequence { α } ( x ) as follows α = β + 1, { α } ( x ) = β , for all x α = ω β +1 , { α } ( x ) = ω β · x α = ω β , where β is a limit ordinal, { α } ( x ) = ω { β } ( x ) α = ω β · ( a + 1), where a � = 1, { α } ( x ) = ω β · a + { ω β } ( x ) α with Cantor normal form ending in ω β · a , say α = γ + ω β · a , { α } ( x ) = γ + { ω β · a } ( x ) 6

  8. Sequence of ordinals cofinal in ǫ 0 ω 0 = 1 and ω n +1 = ω ω n Sommer in 95 formalizes the whole theory of ordinals below ǫ 0 in I ∆ 0 , including the notion of fundamental sequence, Cantor normal form, ω n ’s Defn: A sequence J = x 1 < x 2 < . . . is α - large if there is (a code for) a computation sequence C = < c 0 , c 1 , . . . , c 2 r +2 > where c 2 i is a decreasing sequence of ordinals, c 2 i +1 = x i ∈ J and c 0 = α , c 1 = x 0 , and c 2( i +1) = { c 2 i } ( c 2 i +1 ) and c 2 r +2 = 0. Notation: ( J, C ) α Example: The set X = { 3 , 4 , 5 , 6 } is ω -large, ω (3 , 4 , 5 , 6) = 3(4 , 5 , 6) = 2(5 , 6) = 1(6) = 0( ∅ ) = 0 giving the computation sequence C = < ω, 3 , 3 , 4 , 2 , 5 , 1 , 6 , 0 > . Sommer has α -largeness in I ∆ 0 + exp 7

  9. Properties: 1. If J is α -large, where α = ω β 1 x 1 + . . . + ω β n x n then J = J n ˆ · · · ˆ J 1 , where J i is ω β i x i -large. 2. If ( J, C ) ω α then there exists J ′ ⊆ J and C ′ such that ( J ′ , C ′ ) α If C ′ = ( α, x 0 , β 1 , x 1 , . . . , β r − 1 , x r , 0) then there is a subsequence C ′′ of C C ′′ = ( ω α , x 0 , ω β 1 , x 1 , . . . , ω β r − 1 x r , ω 0 ), 3. If ( J, C ) ω α · x then for all y < x , the ordinal ω α · y appears in C . 4. If J is ω n +2 -large, with first element ≥ c , then there exists J ′ ⊆ J that is ( ω n +1 + ω 3 + c + 3)-large. 5. ( J, C ) α and j 0 1st element of J then for all x ≤ j 0 there is i s.t. { α } ( x ) = α 2 i x -unwinding of α 6. If J is cofinal definable then J is α -large for all α < ǫ 0 8

  10. Connections with Ramsey theory by Ketonen and Solovay Thm (Inductive lemma) Let n ≥ 1 and let ω ≤ α < ǫ 0 . Suppose F : J [ n +1] → c . If J is θ -large, where θ = ω α + ω 3 + max { c, || α ||} +3, then there is an α -large set I ⊆ J such that for increasing tuples x, y and x, z in J n +1 , F ( x, y ) = F ( x, z ). where || 0 || = 0 and if α = ω α 1 m 1 + . . . + ω α k m k , then || α || = � k j =1 m j · ( || α j || + 1) Cor (pigeon-hole principle) Let F : J → c . If J is θ -large, where θ = ω α +1 + ω 3 + max { c, || α ||} + 3, then there is an α -large set I ⊆ J on which F is constant. 9

  11. The following simple but wasteful version of Inductive lemma e pigeonhole principle hold Thm (Inductive lemma) Suppose F : J [ n +1] → c , where J is ω k +2 -large and min ( J ) ≥ c . Then there is an ω k -large I ⊆ J such that for in- creasing tuples x, y and x, z in J n +1 , F ( x, y ) = F ( x, z ), or even ( ω k + 1)-large. Cor (pigeon-hole principle) Suppose F : J → c , where J is ω k +2 -large and min ( J ) ≥ c . Then there is an ω k -large I ⊆ J on which F is con- stant. There is also a set that is ( ω k +1)-large. Ramsey Theorem for α -largeness Suppose n ≥ Let F : J [ n ] → c , where J is ω k +2 n -large, 1. consisting of elements ≥ c . Then there is an ω k -large, or even ( ω k + 1)-large homogeneous set I ⊆ J . 10

  12. Thm. Let A be a model of PA . Let Γ be a finite subset of formulas with the free variables split. Let r ∈ N . If J is ( ω 1+2 n ( r − 1) + 1)-large, = x < y → g Γ ( x ) < y , then and for x, y ∈ J , A | there is a subset of J of size r that is diagonal indiscernible for all elements of Γ (n=max length of tuples, g Γ primitive recursive function bounding the number of equivalence classes). 11

  13. Wainer hierarchy: For α < ǫ 0 , F α ( x ) is defined as follows F 0 ( x ) = x + 1, F α +1 ( x ) = F ( x +1) ( x ), α F α ( x ) = max { F { α } ( j ) ( x ) : j ≤ x } for α a limit ordinal Ketonen and Solovay related the notion of α - largeness to the functions of the Wainer Hier- archy. They introduce the function G α ( x ) = µy ([ x, y ] is α − large), Thm. For any α < ǫ 0 (i) F α ( n ) ≤ G ω α ( n + 1); (ii) G ω α ( n ) ≤ F α ( n + 1) Sommer proves Theorem in I ∆ 0 + exp . 12

  14. Refinements of McAloon Thm (McAloon, Som- mer, D’A., Paris, Dimitracopoulos) Let A be a model of I ∆ 0 , and let a be a non- standard element. TFAE: 1) there is an initial segment B of A such that a ∈ B and B is a model of PA ; 2) there is an infinite set I of order type ω , con- sisting of elements greater than a , such that = i 2 < j , and I is diagonal if i < j in I , A | indiscernible for all ϕ ( u, x ) in B 0 ; 3) there exist b and c s.t. c codes satisfaction of bounded formulas by tuples < b , and for all finite r , there is a sequence I r of size r , with = i 2 < j , and I r a < I r < b , s.t. if i < j in I r , A | is diagonal indiscernible for the first r elements of B 0 , 4) there exists b s.t. for all α < ǫ 0 , F α ( a ) ↓ < b . 13

  15. Defn. Let A and B be L -structures. We say that B is an n -elementary substructure of A if for all B n - formulas ϕ ( x ) and all b in B , B | = ϕ ( b ) iff A | = ϕ ( b ). Notation: B ≤ n A , Tarski Criterion: Let B ≤ 0 A , and let n > 0. Suppose that for all B n − 1 formulas ϕ ( x, u ), and for all b in B if there exists d ∈ A such that = ϕ ( b, d ), then there exists d ′ in B such that A | = ϕ ( b, d ′ ). Then B ≤ n A . A | Defn. Let A be a L -structure and let ϕ ( u, x ) be a formula with the free variables splitted into u and x . We say that I bounds witnesses for ϕ ( u, x ) if for all i, j ∈ I such that A | = i < j , and all a ≤ i in A , A | = ( ∃ x ) ϕ ( a, x ) → ( ∃ x ≤ j ) ϕ ( a, x ) . 14

  16. QUESTIONS: 1) Give necessary and sufficient conditions for an initial segment B of A model of I ∆ 0 to be a model of PA and n -elementary substructure of A 2) When does a ∈ A belong to an initial seg- ment B of A model of PA and n -elementary substructure of A ? Lemma: Let A be a model of I ∆ 0 , and let n > 0. Suppose I ⊆ A is a set of order type ω that is diagonal indiscernible for all elements of B 0 and bounds witnesses for all elements of B n − 1 . Let B be the downward closure of I . Then is a model of PA and B ≤ n A . In order to guarantee the existence of such el- ements we distinguish two cases: Case 1: N ≤ n A Case 2: N �≤ n A 15

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend