iterated ultrapowers and automorphisms ali enayat pisa
play

Iterated Ultrapowers and Automorphisms Ali Enayat Pisa, May 2006 1 - PDF document

Iterated Ultrapowers and Automorphisms Ali Enayat Pisa, May 2006 1 Our story begins with: Question (H asenj ager): Does PA have a model with a nontrivial auto- morphism? Answer (Ehrenfeucht and Mostowski): Yes, indeed given any


  1. Iterated Ultrapowers and Automorphisms Ali Enayat Pisa, May 2006 1

  2. Our story begins with: • Question (H¨ asenj¨ ager): Does PA have a model with a nontrivial auto- morphism? • Answer (Ehrenfeucht and Mostowski): Yes, indeed given any first order theory T with an infinite model M � T , and any linear order L , there is a model M L of T such that Aut ( L ) ֒ → Aut ( M L ) . • Corollaries: (a) PA , RCF, and ZFC have models with rich automorphism groups. (b) Nonstandard models of analysis with rich automorphism groups exist. 2

  3. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (1) • Gaifman saw a radically different proof of the EM Theorem: iterate the ultrapower construction along a prescribed linear order. • Suppose (a) M = ( M, · · · ) is a structure, (b) U is an ultrafilter over P ( N ), and (c) L is a linear order. we wish to describe the L -iterated ultrapower � M ∗ := M . U , L 3

  4. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers, Continued (2) • A key definition (reminiscent of Fubini): ( X ) a � �� � U 2 := { X ⊆ N 2 : { a ∈ N : { b ∈ N : ( a, b ) ∈ X }∈ U} ∈ U . • More generally, for each n ∈ N + : U n +1 := { X ⊆ N n +1 : { a ∈ N : ( X ) a ∈ U n } ∈ U} , where ( X ) a := { ( b 1 , · · · , b n ) : ( a, b 1 , · · · , b n ) ∈ X } 4

  5. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (3) • Let Υ be the set of terms τ of the form f ( l 1 , · · · , l n ) , where n ∈ N + , f : N n → M and ( l 1 , · · · , l n ) ∈ [ L ] n . • The universe M ∗ of M ∗ consists of equivalence classes { [ τ ] : τ ∈ Υ } , where the equivalence relation ∼ at work is defined as follows: given ′ ′ f ( l 1 , · · · , l r ) and g ( l 1 , · · · , l s ) from Υ, first suppose that � � ′ ′ ∈ [ L ] r + s ; l 1 , · · · , l r , l 1 , · · · , l s ′ ′ let p := r + s , and define: f ( l 1 , · · · , l r ) ∼ g ( l 1 , · · · , l s ) iff: { ( i 1 , · · · , i p ) ∈ N p : f ( i 1 , · · · , i r ) = g ( i r +1 , · · · , i p ) } ∈ U p . 5

  6. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (4) More generally: ′ ′ • Given f ( l 1 , · · · , l r ) and g ( l 1 , · · · , l s ) from Υ , let ′ ′ P := { l 1 , · · · , l r } ∪ { l 1 , · · · , l s } , p := | P | , and relabel the elements of P in increasing order as l 1 < · · · < l p . This relabelling gives rise to increasing sequences ( j 1 , j 2 , · · · , j r ) and ( k 1 , k 2 , · · · , k s ) of indices between 1 and p such that l 1 = l j 1 , l 2 = l j 2 , · · · , l r = l j r and l ′ ′ ′ 1 = l k 1 , l 2 = l k 2 , · · · , l s = l k s . ′ ′ Then define: f ( l 1 , · · · , l r ) ∼ g ( l 1 , · · · , l s ) iff { ( i 1 , · · · , i p ) ∈ N p : f ( i j 1 , · · · , i j r ) = g ( i k 1 , · · · , i k s ) } ∈ U p . 6

  7. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (5) • We can also use the previous relabelling to define the operations and relations of M ∗ as follows, e.g., [ f ( l 1 , · · · , l r )] ⊙ M ∗ [ g ( l ′ ′ 1 , · · · , l s )] := [ v ( l 1 , · · · , l p )] where v : N n → M by v ( i 1 , · · · , i p ) := f ( i j 1 , · · · , i j r ) ⊙ M g ( i k 1 , · · · , i k s ); [ f ( l 1 , · · · , l r )] ⊳ M ∗ [ g ( l ′ ′ 1 , · · · , l s )] iff { ( i 1 , · · · , i p ) ∈ N p : f ( i j 1 , · · · , i j r ) ⊳ M ∗ g ( i k 1 , · · · , i k s ) } ∈ U p . The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (6) • For m ∈ M , let c m be the constant m -function on N , i.e. , c m : N → { m } . For any l ∈ L , we can identify the element [ c m ( l )] with m . • We shall also identify [ id ( l )] with l, where id : N → N is the identity function (WLOG N ⊆ M ) . • Therefore M ∪ L can be viewed as a subset of M ∗ . 7

  8. • Theorem. For every formula ϕ ( x 1 , ··· , x n ) , and every ( l 1 , · · · , l n ) ∈ [ L ] n : M ∗ � ϕ ( l 1 , l 2 , · · · , l n ) ⇐ ⇒ { ( i 1 , · · · , i n ) ∈ N n : M � ϕ ( i 1 , · · · , i n ) } ∈ U n . The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (7) • Corollary 1. M ≺ M ∗ , and L is a set of order indiscernibles in M ∗ . • Corollary 2. Every automorphism j of L lifts to an automorphism ˆ  of M ∗ via ˆ  ([ f ( l 1 , · · · , l n )]) = [ f ( j ( l 1 ) , · · · , j ( l n ))] . Moreover, the map j �→ ˆ  is a group embedding of Aut ( L ) into Aut ( M ∗ ) . 8

  9. Skolem-Gaifman Ultrapowers (1) • If M has definable Skolem functions, then we can form the Skolem ultrapower � M F , U as follows: (a) Suppose B is the Boolean algebra of parametrically definable subsets of M , and U is an ultrafilter over B . (b) Let F be the family of functions from M into M that are paramet- rically definable in M . (c) The universe of the M ∗ is { [ f ] : f ∈ F} , where f ∼ g ⇐ ⇒ { m ∈ M : f ( m ) = g ( m ) } ∈ U 9

  10. Skolem-Gaifman Ultrapowers (2) • Theorem (MacDowell-Specker) Every model of PA has an elementary end extension. Proof : for an appropriate choice of U , � M ≺ e M . F , U • For models of some Skolemized theories, such as PA , the process of ultrapower formation can be iterated along any linear order. • For each parametrically definable X ⊆ M, and m ∈ M, ( X ) m = { x ∈ M : � m, x � ∈ X } . • U is an iterable ultrafilter over B if for every definable X ⊆ M , { m ∈ M : ( X ) m ∈ U} . 10

  11. Skolem-Gaifman Ultrapowers (3) • Theorem (Gaifman) If U is iterable, and L is a linear order, then � M ≺ e, cons M . F , U , L • Theorem (Gaifman). For an appropriate choice of iterable U , (a) Aut ( � M ; M ) ∼ = Aut ( L ) . F , U , L � (b) M has an automorphism j such that F , U , L fix ( j ) = M. • Theorem (Schmerl). Suppose G ≤ Aut ( L ) for some linear order L . (a) G ∼ = Aut ( M ) for some M � PA. (b) G ∼ = Aut ( F ) for some ordered field F . 11

  12. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (1) • A cut I of M � PA is an initial segment of M with no last element . • For a cut I of M , SSy I ( M ) is the collection of sets of the form X ∩ I, where X is parametrically definable in M . • I is strong in M iff ( I , SSy I ( M )) � ACA 0 . • M is recursively saturated if for every m ∈ M, every recursive finitely realizable type over ( M , m ) is realized in M . • For j ∈ Aut ( M ) , I fix ( j ) := { x ∈ dom ( j ) : ∀ y ≤ x j ( y ) = y } , fix ( j ) := { x ∈ M : j ( x ) = x } 12

  13. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (2) Suppose M � PA is ctble, rec. sat., and I is a cut of M . • Theorem (Smory´ nski) I = I fix ( j ) for some j ∈ Aut ( M ) iff I is closed under exponentiation . • Theorem (Kaye-Kossak-Kotlarski ) I = fix ( j ) for some j ∈ Aut ( M ) iff I is a strong elementary submodel of M . 13

  14. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (3) • Theorem (Kaye-Kossak-Kotlarski) N isstrongin M � �� � M isarithmeticallysaturated iff for some j ∈ Aut ( M ), jismaximal � �� � fix ( j ) isthecollectionofdefinableelementsof M . • Theorem (Schmerl) Aut ( Q ) ֒ → Aut ( M ) . 14

  15. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (4) • Theorem (E). If I is a closed under exponentiation, then there is a group embedding j �→ ˆ  from Aut ( Q ) into Aut ( M ) such that: (a) I fix (ˆ  ) = I for every nontrivial j ∈ Aut ( Q );  ) ∼ (b) fix(ˆ = M for every fixed point free j ∈ Aut ( Q ) . • Idea of the proof: Fix c ∈ M \ I, let c := { x ∈ M : x < c } , B := P M ( c ), and F be the family of functions from ( c ) n → M that are coded in M . For an appropriate choice of U , � M ∼ M overI. = F , U , Q This sort of iteration was implicitly considered by Mills and Paris. 15

  16. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (5) • A new type of iteration that subsumes both Gaifman and Paris-Mills iteration: starting with I ⊆ e M � N , withI ⊆ strong N , (a) F = { f ↾ I n : f par. definable in N } ; (b) B := SSy I ( N ); (c) U an appropriate ultrafilter over B . • Theorem (E). Suppose M is arithmetically saturated. There is a group embedding j �→ ˆ  from Aut ( Q ) into Aut ( M ) such that ˆ  is maximal for every fixed point free j ∈ Aut ( Q ) . 16

  17. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (6) • Conjecture (Schmerl). Suppose M is arithmetically saturated, and M 0 ≺ M . Then fix ( j ) ∼ = M 0 for some j ∈ Aut ( M ) . • Theorem (Kossak) Every countable model of PA is isomorphic to some fix ( j ), for some j ∈ Aut ( M ), and some countable arithmetically satu- rated model M . • Theorem (Kossak) The cardinality of { fix ( j ) : j ∈ Aut ( M ) } / ∼ = is either 2 ℵ 0 or 1, depending on whether M is arithmetically saturated or not. • Theorem (E). Suppose M 0 ≺ M , and M is arithmetically saturated . There are M 1 ≺ M with M 0 ∼ = M 1 , and an embedding j �→ ˆ  of Aut ( Q ) into Aut ( M ), such that fix(ˆ  ) = M 1 for every fixed point free j ∈ Aut ( Q ) . 17

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend