a game theoretic ergodic theorem for imprecise markov
play

A game-theoretic ergodic theorem for imprecise Markov chains Gert - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

A game-theoretic ergodic theorem for imprecise Markov chains Gert de Cooman Ghent University, SYSTeMS gert.decooman@UGent.be http://users.UGent.be/gdcooma gertekoo.wordpress.com GTP 2014 CIMAT, Guanajuato 13 November 2014 My boon


  1. A game-theoretic ergodic theorem for imprecise Markov chains Gert de Cooman Ghent University, SYSTeMS gert.decooman@UGent.be http://users.UGent.be/˜gdcooma gertekoo.wordpress.com GTP 2014 CIMAT, Guanajuato 13 November 2014

  2. My boon companions FILIP HERMANS ENRIQUE MIRANDA JASPER DE BOCK

  3. Jean Ville and martingales

  4. The original definition of a martingale Étude critique de la notion de collectif, 1939, p. 83

  5. In a (perhaps) more modern notation Ville’s definition of a martingale A martingale s is a sequence of real functions s o , s 1 ( X 1 ) , s 2 ( X 1 , X 2 ) , . . . such that 1 s o = 1 ; 2 s n ( X 1 ,..., X n ) ≥ 0 for all n ∈ N ; 3 E ( s n + 1 ( x 1 ,..., x n , X n + 1 ) | x 1 ,..., x n ) = s n ( x 1 ,..., x n ) for all n ∈ N 0 and all x 1 ,..., x n . It represents the outcome of a fair betting scheme, without borrowing (or bankruptcy).

  6. Ville’s theorem The collection of all (locally defined!) martingales determines the probability P on the sample space Ω : P ( A ) = sup { λ ∈ R : s martingale and limsup λ s n ( X 1 ,..., X n ) ≤ I A } n → + ∞ = inf { λ ∈ R : s martingale and liminf n → + ∞ λ s n ( X 1 ,..., X n ) ≥ I A }

  7. Ville’s theorem The collection of all (locally defined!) martingales determines the probability P on the sample space Ω : P ( A ) = sup { λ ∈ R : s martingale and limsup λ s n ( X 1 ,..., X n ) ≤ I A } n → + ∞ = inf { λ ∈ R : s martingale and liminf n → + ∞ λ s n ( X 1 ,..., X n ) ≥ I A } Turning things around Ville’s theorem suggests that we could take a convex set of martingales as a primitive notion, and probabilities and expectations as derived notions. That we need an convex set of them, elucidates that martingales are examples of partial probability assessments.

  8. Imprecise probabilities: dealing with partial probability assessments

  9. Partial probability assessments lower and/or upper bounds for – the probabilities of a number of events, – the expectations of a number of random variables

  10. Partial probability assessments lower and/or upper bounds for – the probabilities of a number of events, – the expectations of a number of random variables Imprecise probability models A partial assessment generally does not determine a probability measure uniquely, only a convex closed set of them.

  11. Partial probability assessments lower and/or upper bounds for – the probabilities of a number of events, – the expectations of a number of random variables Imprecise probability models A partial assessment generally does not determine a probability measure uniquely, only a convex closed set of them. IP Theory systematic way of dealing with, representing, and making conservative inferences based on partial probability assessments

  12. Lower and upper expectations

  13. Lower and upper expectations A Subject is uncertain about the value that a variable X assumes in X . Gambles: A gamble f : X → R is an uncertain reward whose value is f ( X ) . G ( X ) denotes the set of all gambles on X .

  14. Lower and upper expectations A Subject is uncertain about the value that a variable X assumes in X . Gambles: A gamble f : X → R is an uncertain reward whose value is f ( X ) . G ( X ) denotes the set of all gambles on X . Lower and upper expectations: A lower expectation is a real functional that satisfies: E1. E ( f ) ≥ inf f [bounds] E2. E ( f + g ) ≥ E ( f )+ E ( g ) [superadditivity] E3. E ( λ f ) = λ E ( f ) for all real λ ≥ 0 [non-negative homogeneity] E ( f ) : = − E ( − f ) defines the conjugate upper expectation.

  15. Sub- and supermartingales

  16. An event tree and its situations Situations are nodes in the event tree, and the sample space Ω is the set of all terminal situations: ω terminal initial t non-terminal

  17. Events An event A is a subset of the sample space Ω : s Γ ( s ) : = { ω ∈ Ω : s ⊑ ω }

  18. Local, or immediate prediction, models In each non-terminal situation s , Subject has a belief model Q ( ·| s ) . t c 1 Q ( ·| t ) on G ( D ( t )) s Q ( ·| s ) on G ( D ( s )) c 2 D ( s ) = { c 1 , c 2 } is the set of daughters of s .

  19. Sub- and supermartingales We can use the local models Q ( ·| s ) to define sub- and supermartingales: A submartingale M is a real process such that in all non-terminal situations s : Q ( M ( s · ) | s ) ≥ M ( s ) . A supermartingale M is a real process such that in all non-terminal situations s : Q ( M ( s · ) | s ) ≤ M ( s ) .

  20. Lower and upper expectations The most conservative lower and upper expectations on G ( Ω ) that coincide with the local models and satisfy a number of additional continuity criteria (cut conglomerability and cut continuity): Conditional lower expectations: E ( f | s ) : = sup { M ( s ) : limsup M ≤ f on Γ ( s ) } Conditional upper expectations: E ( f | s ) : = inf { M ( s ) : liminf M ≥ f on Γ ( s ) }

  21. Test supermartingales and strictly null events A test supermartingale T is a non-negative supermartingale with T ( � ) = 1 . (Very close to Ville’s definition of a martingale.) An event A is strictly null if there is some test supermartingale T that converges to + ∞ on A : n → ∞ T ( ω n ) = + ∞ for all ω ∈ A . lim T ( ω ) = lim If A is strictly null then P ( A ) = E ( I A ) = inf { M ( � ) : liminf M ≥ I A } = 0 .

  22. A few basic limit results Supermartingale convergence theorem [Shafer and Vovk, 2001] A supermartingale M that is bounded below converges strictly almost surely to a real number: liminf M ( ω ) = limsup M ( ω ) ∈ R strictly almost surely .

  23. A few basic limit results Strong law of large numbers for submartingale differences [De Cooman and De Bock, 2013] Consider any submartingale M such that its difference process ∆ M ( s ) = M ( s · ) − M ( s ) ∈ G ( D ( s )) for all non-terminal s is uniformly bounded. Then liminf � M � ≥ 0 strictly almost surely, where � M � ( ω n ) = 1 n M ( ω n ) for all ω ∈ Ω and n ∈ N

  24. A few basic limit results Lévy’s zero–one law [Shafer, Vovk and Takemura, 2012] For any bounded real gamble f on Ω : E ( f | ω n ) ≤ f ( ω ) ≤ liminf n → + ∞ E ( f | ω n ) strictly almost surely . limsup n → + ∞

  25. Imprecise Markov chains

  26. A simple discrete-time finite-state stochastic process ( b , b , b ) Q ( ·| b , b ) ( b , b ) ( b , b , a ) Q ( ·| b ) b ( b , a , b ) ( b , a ) Q ( ·| b , a ) ( b , a , a ) Q ( ·| � ) ( a , b , b ) Q ( ·| a , b ) ( a , b ) ( a , b , a ) Q ( ·| a ) a ( a , a , b ) ( a , a ) Q ( ·| a , a ) ( a , a , a )

  27. An imprecise IID model ( b , b , b ) Q ( ·| � ) ( b , b ) ( b , b , a ) Q ( ·| � ) b ( b , a , b ) ( b , a ) Q ( ·| � ) ( b , a , a ) Q ( ·| � ) ( a , b , b ) Q ( ·| � ) ( a , b ) ( a , b , a ) Q ( ·| � ) a ( a , a , b ) ( a , a ) Q ( ·| � ) ( a , a , a )

  28. An imprecise Markov chain ( b , b , b ) Q ( ·| b ) ( b , b ) ( b , b , a ) Q ( ·| b ) b ( b , a , b ) ( b , a ) Q ( ·| a ) ( b , a , a ) Q ( ·| � ) ( a , b , b ) Q ( ·| b ) ( a , b ) ( a , b , a ) Q ( ·| a ) a ( a , a , b ) ( a , a ) Q ( ·| a ) ( a , a , a )

  29. Stationarity and ergodicity The lower expectation E n for the state X n at time n : E n ( f ) = E ( f ( X n )) The imprecise Markov chain is Perron–Frobenius-like if for all marginal models E 1 and all f : E n ( f ) → E ∞ ( f ) . and if E 1 = E ∞ then E n = E ∞ , and the imprecise Markov chain is stationary. In any Perron–Frobenius-like imprecise Markov chain: n 1 ∑ E n ( f ) = E ∞ ( f ) lim n → + ∞ n k = 1 and n n 1 1 f ( X k ) ≤ E ∞ ( f ) str. almost surely . ∑ ∑ E ∞ ( f ) ≤ liminf f ( X k ) ≤ limsup n n n → + ∞ n → + ∞ k = 1 k = 1

  30. A more general ergodic theorem: the basics Introduce a shift operator: θω = θ ( x 1 , x 2 , x 3 ,... ) : = ( x 2 , x 3 , x 4 ,... ) for all ω ∈ Ω , and for any gamble f on Ω a shifted gamble θ f : = f ◦ θ : ( θ f )( ω ) : = f ( θω ) for all ω ∈ Ω . For any bounded gamble f on Ω , the bounded gambles: n − 1 n − 1 1 1 θ k f and g = limsup θ k f ∑ ∑ g = liminf n → + ∞ n n n → + ∞ k = 0 k = 0 are shift-invariant: θ g = g .

  31. A more general ergodic theorem: use Lévy’s zero–one law In any Perron–Frobenius-like imprecise Markov chain, for any shift-invariant gamble g = θ g on Ω : n → + ∞ E ( g | ω n ) = E ∞ ( g ) and n → + ∞ E ( g | ω n ) = E ∞ ( g ) lim lim and therefore E ∞ ( g ) ≤ g ≤ E ∞ ( g ) strictly almost surely .

  32. New books

Download Presentation
Download Policy: The content available on the website is offered to you 'AS IS' for your personal information and use only. It cannot be commercialized, licensed, or distributed on other websites without prior consent from the author. To download a presentation, simply click this link. If you encounter any difficulties during the download process, it's possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.

Recommend


More recommend